关键词不能为空

当前您在: 主页 > 英语 >

METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS OF ETHICS

作者:高考题库网
来源:https://www.bjmy2z.cn/gaokao
2021-02-11 20:57
tags:

-

2021年2月11日发(作者:元吉)









































1780
























THE METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS OF ETHICS


































by Immanuel Kant























translated by Thomas Kingsmill Abbott


PREFACE



























PREFACE





If there exists on any subject a philosophy (that is, a system of


rational knowledge based on concepts), then there must also be for


this philosophy a system of pure rational concepts, independent of any


condition of intuition, in other words, a metaphysic. It may be


asked whether metaphysical elements are required also for every


practical philosophy, which is the doctrine of duties, and therefore


also for Ethics, in order to be able to present it as a true science


(systematically), not merely as an aggregate of separate doctrines


(fragmentarily). As regards pure jurisprudence, no one will question


this requirement; for it concerns only what is formal in the


elective will, which has to be limited in its external relations


according to laws of freedom; without regarding any end which is the


matter of this will. Here, therefore, deontology is a mere


scientific doctrine (doctrina scientiae).*





*One who is acquainted with practical philosophy is not,


therefore, a practical philosopher. The latter is he who makes the


rational end the principle of his actions, while at the same time he


joins with this the necessary knowledge which, as it aims at action,


must not be spun out into the most subtile threads of metaphysic,


unless a legal duty is in question; in which case meum and tuum must


be accurately determined in the balance of justice, on the principle


of equality of action and action, which requires something like


mathematical proportion, but not in the case of a mere ethical duty.


For in this case the question is not only to know what it is a duty to


do (a thing which on account of the ends that all men naturally have


can be easily decided), but the chief point is the inner principle


of the will namely that the consciousness of this duty be also the


spring of action, in order that we may be able to say of the man who


joins to his knowledge this principle of wisdom that he is a practical


philosopher.





Now in this philosophy (of ethics) it seems contrary to the idea


of it that we should go back to metaphysical elements in order to make


the notion of duty purified from everything empirical (from every


feeling) a motive of action. For what sort of notion can we form of


the mighty power and herculean strength which would be sufficient to


1




overcome the vice-breeding inclinations, if Virtue is to borrow her



speculation that only few men can handle? Hence all ethical teaching


in lecture rooms, pulpits, and popular books, when it is decked out


with fragments of metaphysics, becomes ridiculous. But it is not,


therefore, useless, much less ridiculous, to trace in metaphysics


the first principles of ethics; for it is only as a philosopher that


anyone can reach the first principles of this conception of duty,


otherwise we could not look for either certainty or purity in the


ethical teaching. To rely for this reason on a certain feeling


which, on account of the effect expected from it, is called moral,


may, perhaps, even satisfy the popular teacher, provided he desires as


the criterion of a moral duty to consider the problem:


every case made your maxim the universal law, how could this law be


consistent with itself?


our duty to take this principle as a criterion, then this would not be


dictated by reason, but only adopted instinctively and therefore


blindly.




But in fact, whatever men imagine, no moral principle is based on


any feeling, but such a principle is really nothing else than an


obscurely conceived metaphysic which inheres in every man's


reasoning faculty; as the teacher will easily find who tries to


catechize his pupils in the Socratic method about the imperative of


duty and its application to the moral judgement of his actions. The


mode of stating it need not be always metaphysical, and the language


need not necessarily be scholastic, unless the pupil is to be


trained to be a philosopher. But the thought must go back to the


elements of metaphysics, without which we cannot expect any


certainty or purity, or even motive power in ethics.




If we deviate from this principle and begin from pathological, or


purely sensitive, or even moral feeling (from what is subjectively


practical instead of what is objective), that is, from the matter of


the will, the end, not from its form that is the law, in order from


thence to determine duties; then, certainly, there are no metaphysical


elements of ethics, for feeling by whatever it may be excited is


always physical. But then ethical teaching, whether in schools, or


lecture-rooms, etc., is corrupted in its source. For it is not a


matter of indifference by what motives or means one is led to a good


purpose (the obedience to duty). However disgusting, then, metaphysics


may appear to those pretended philosophers who dogmatize oracularly,


or even brilliantly, about the doctrine of duty, it is,


nevertheless, an indispensable duty for those who oppose it to go back


to its principles even in ethics, and to begin by going to school on


its benches.


2







We may fairly wonder how, after all previous explanations of the


principles of duty, so far as it is derived from pure reason, it was


still possible to reduce it again to a doctrine of happiness; in


such a way, however, that a certain moral happiness not resting on


empirical causes was ultimately arrived at, a self-contradictory


nonentity. In fact, when the thinking man has conquered the


temptations to vice, and is conscious of having done his (often


hard) duty, he finds himself in a state of peace and satisfaction


which may well be called happiness, in which virtue is her own reward.


Now, says the eudaemonist, this delight, this happiness, is the real


motive of his acting virtuously. The notion of duty, says be, does not


immediately determine his will; it is only by means of the happiness


in prospect that he is moved to his duty. Now, on the other hand,


since he can promise himself this reward of virtue only from the


consciousness of having done his duty, it is clear that the latter


must have preceded: that is, be must feel himself bound to do his duty


before he thinks, and without thinking, that happiness will be the


consequence of obedience to duty. He is thus involved in a circle in


his assignment of cause and effect. He can only hope to be happy if he


is conscious of his obedience to duty: and he can only be moved to


obedience to duty if be foresees that he will thereby become happy.


But in this reasoning there is also a contradiction. For, on the one


side, he must obey his duty, without asking what effect this will have


on his happiness, consequently, from a moral principle; on the other


side, he can only recognize something as his duty when he can reckon


on happiness which will accrue to him thereby, and consequently on a


pathological principle, which is the direct opposite of the former.




I have in another place (the Berlin Monatsschrift), reduced, as I


believe, to the simplest expressions the distinction between


pathological and moral pleasure. The pleasure, namely, which must


precede the obedience to the law in order that one may act according


to the law is pathological, and the process follows the physical order


of nature; that which must be preceded by the law in order that it may


be felt is in the moral order. If this distinction is not observed; if


eudaemonism (the principle of happiness) is adopted as the principle


instead of eleutheronomy (the principle of freedom of the inner


legislation), the consequence is the euthanasia (quiet death) of all


morality.




The cause of these mistakes is no other than the following: Those


who are accustomed only to physiological explanations will not admit


into their heads the categorical imperative from which these laws


dictatorially proceed, notwithstanding that they feel themselves


irresistibly forced by it. Dissatisfied at not being able to explain


3




what lies wholly beyond that sphere, namely, freedom of the elective


will, elevating as is this privilege, that man has of being capable of


such an idea. They are stirred up by the proud claims of speculative


reason, which feels its power so strongly in the fields, just as if


they were allies leagued in defence of the omnipotence of


theoretical reason and roused by a general call to arms to resist that


idea; and thus they are at present, and perhaps for a long time to


come, though ultimately in vain, to attack the moral concept of


freedom and if possible render it doubtful.


INTRODUCTION








INTRODUCTION TO THE METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS OF ETHICS





Ethics in ancient times signified moral philosophy (philosophia


moral is) generally, which was also called the doctrine of duties.


Subsequently it was found advisable to confine this name to a part


of moral philosophy, namely, to the doctrine of duties which are not


subject to external laws (for which in German the name Tugendlehre was


found suitable). Thus the system of general deontology is divided into


that of jurisprudence (jurisprudentia), which is capable of external


laws, and of ethics, which is not thus capable, and we may let this


division stand.






I. Exposition of the Conception of Ethics





The notion of duty is in itself already the notion of a constraint


of the free elective will by the law; whether this constraint be an


external one or be self-constraint. The moral imperative, by its


categorical (the unconditional ought) announces this constraint, which


therefore does not apply to all rational beings (for there may also be


holy beings), but applies to men as rational physical beings who are


unholy enough to be seduced by pleasure to the transgression of the


moral law, although they themselves recognize its authority; and


when they do obey it, to obey it unwillingly (with resistance of their


inclination); and it is in this that the constraint properly


consists.* Now, as man is a free (moral) being, the notion of duty can


contain only self-constraint (by the idea of the law itself), when


we look to the internal determination of the will (the spring), for


thus only is it possible to combine that constraint (even if it were


external) with the freedom of the elective will. The notion of duty


then must be an ethical one.





*Man, however, as at the same time a moral being, when he


considers himself objectively, which he is qualified to do by his pure


4




practical reason, (i.e., according to humanity in his own person).


finds himself holy enough to transgress the law only unwillingly;


for there is no man so depraved who in this transgression would not


feel a resistance and an abhorrence of himself, so that he must put


a force on himself. It is impossible to explain the phenomenon that at


this parting of the ways (where the beautiful fable places Hercules


between virtue and sensuality) man shows more propensity to obey


inclination than the law. For, we can only explain what happens by


tracing it to a cause according to physical laws; but then we should


not be able to conceive the elective will as free. Now this mutually


opposed self-constraint and the inevitability of it makes us recognize


the incomprehensible property of freedom.





The impulses of nature, then, contain hindrances to the fulfilment


of duty in the mind of man, and resisting forces, some of them


powerful; and he must judge himself able to combat these and to


conquer them by means of reason, not in the future, but in the


present, simultaneously with the thought; he must judge that he can do


what the law unconditionally commands that be ought.




Now the power and resolved purpose to resist a strong but unjust


opponent is called fortitude (fortitudo), and when concerned with


the opponent of the moral character within us, it is virtue (virtus,


fortitudo moralis). Accordingly, general deontology, in that part


which brings not external, but internal, freedom under laws is the


doctrine of virtue.




Jurisprudence had to do only with the formal condition of external


freedom (the condition of consistency with itself, if its maxim became


a universal law), that is, with law. Ethics, on the contrary, supplies


us with a matter (an object of the free elective will), an end of pure


reason which is at the same time conceived as an objectively necessary


end, i.e., as duty for all men. For, as the sensible inclinations


mislead us to ends (which are the matter of the elective will) that


may contradict duty, the legislating reason cannot otherwise guard


against their influence than by an opposite moral end, which therefore


must be given a priori independently on inclination.




An end is an object of the elective will (of a rational being) by


the idea of which this will is determined to an action for the


production of this object. Now I may be forced by others to actions


which are directed to an end as means, but I cannot be forced to


have an end; I can only make something an end to myself. If,


however, I am also bound to make something which lies in the notions


of practical reason an end to myself, and therefore besides the formal


determining principle of the elective will (as contained in law) to


have also a material principle, an end which can be opposed to the end


5




derived from sensible impulses; then this gives the notion of an end


which is in itself a duty. The doctrine of this cannot belong to


jurisprudence, but to ethics, since this alone includes in its


conception self-constraint according to moral laws.




For this reason, ethics may also be defined as the system of the


ends of the pure practical reason. The two parts of moral philosophy


are distinguished as treating respectively of ends and of duties of


constraint. That ethics contains duties to the observance of which one


cannot be (physically) forced by others, is merely the consequence


of this, that it is a doctrine of ends, since to be forced to have


ends or to set them before one's self is a contradiction.




Now that ethics is a doctrine of virtue (doctrina officiorum


virtutis) follows from the definition of virtue given above compared


with the obligation, the peculiarity of which has just been shown.


There is in fact no other determination of the elective will, except


that to an end, which in the very notion of it implies that I cannot


even physically be forced to it by the elective will of others.


Another may indeed force me to do something which is not my end (but


only means to the end of another), but he cannot force me to make it


my own end, and yet I can have no end except of my own making. The


latter supposition would be a contradiction- an act of freedom which


yet at the same time would not be free. But there is no


contradiction in setting before one's self an end which is also a


duty: for in this case I constrain myself, and this is quite


consistent with freedom.* But how is such an end possible? That is now


the question. For the possibility of the notion of the thing (viz.,


that it is not self- contradictory) is not enough to prove the


possibility of the thing itself (the objective reality of the notion).





*The less a man can be physically forced, and the more he can be


morally forced (by the mere idea of duty), so much the freer he is.


The man, for example, who is of sufficiently firm resolution and


strong mind not to give up an enjoyment which he has resolved on,


however much loss is shown as resulting therefrom, and who yet desists


from his purpose unhesitatingly, though very reluctantly, when he


finds that it would cause him to neglect an official duty or a sick


father; this man proves his freedom in the highest degree by this very


thing, that he cannot resist the voice of duty.






II. Exposition of the Notion of an End which is also a Duty





We can conceive the relation of end to duty in two ways; either


starting from the end to find the maxim of the dutiful actions; or


6




conversely, setting out from this to find the end which is also


duty. jurisprudence proceeds in the former way. It is left to


everyone's free elective will what end he will choose for his


action. But its maxim is determined a priori; namely, that the freedom


of the agent must be consistent with the freedom of every other


according to a universal law.




Ethics, however, proceeds in the opposite way. It cannot start


from the ends which the man may propose to himself, and hence give


directions as to the maxims he should adopt, that is, as to his


duty; for that would be to take empirical principles of maxims, and


these could not give any notion of duty; since this, the categorical


ought, has its root in pure reason alone. Indeed, if the maxims were


to be adopted in accordance with those ends (which are all selfish),


we could not properly speak of the notion of duty at all. Hence in


ethics the notion of duty must lead to ends, and must on moral


principles give the foundation of maxims with respect to the ends


which we ought to propose to ourselves.




Setting aside the question what sort of end that is which is in


itself a duty, and how such an end is possible, it is here only


necessary to show that a duty of this kind is called a duty of virtue,


and why it is so called.




To every duty corresponds a right of action (facultas moral is


generatim), but all duties do not imply a corresponding right


(facultas juridica) of another to compel any one, but only the


duties called legal duties. Similarly to all ethical obligation


corresponds the notion of virtue, but it does not follow that all


ethical duties are duties of virtue. Those, in fact, are not so


which do not concern so much a certain end (matter, object of the


elective will), but merely that which is formal in the moral


determination of the will (e.g., that the dutiful action must also


be done from duty). It is only an end which is also duty that can be


called a duty of virtue. Hence there are several of the latter kind


(and thus there are distinct virtues); on the contrary, there is


only one duty of the former kind, but it is one which is valid for all


actions (only one virtuous disposition).




The duty of virtue is essentially distinguished from the duty of


justice in this respect; that it is morally possible to be


externally compelled to the latter, whereas the former rests on free


self- constraint only. For finite holy beings (which cannot even be


tempted to the violation of duty) there is no doctrine of virtue,


but only moral philosophy, the latter being an autonomy of practical


reason, whereas the former is also an autocracy of it. That is, it


includes a consciousness- not indeed immediately perceived, but


rightly concluded, from the moral categorical imperative- of the power


7




to become master of one's inclinations which resist the law; so that


human morality in its highest stage can yet be nothing more than


virtue; even if it were quite pure (perfectly free from the


influence of a spring foreign to duty), a state which is poetically


personified under the name of the wise man (as an ideal to which one


should continually approximate).




Virtue, however, is not to be defined and esteemed merely as


habit, and (as it is expressed in the prize essay of Cochius) as a


long custom acquired by practice of morally good actions. For, if this


is not an effect of well-resolved and firm principles ever more and


more purified, then, like any other mechanical arrangement brought


about by technical practical reason, it is neither armed for all


circumstances nor adequately secured against the change that may be


wrought by new allurements.




























REMARK





To virtue = + a is opposed as its logical contradictory


(contradictorie oppositum) the negative lack of virtue (moral


weakness) = o; but vice = a is its contrary (contrarie s. realiter


oppositum); and it is not merely a needless question but an


offensive one to ask whether great crimes do not perhaps demand more


strength of mind than great virtues. For by strength of mind we


understand the strength of purpose of a man, as a being endowed with


freedom, and consequently so far as he is master of himself (in his


senses) and therefore in a healthy condition of mind. But great crimes


are paroxysms, the very sight of which makes the man of healthy mind


shudder. The question would therefore be something like this:


whether a man in a fit of madness can have more physical strength than


if he is in his senses; and we may admit this without on that


account ascribing to him more strength of mind, if by mind we


understand the vital principle of man in the free use of his powers.


For since those crimes have their ground merely in the power of the


inclinations that weaken reason, which does not prove strength of


mind, this question would be nearly the same as the question whether a


man in a fit of illness can show more strength than in a healthy


condition; and this may be directly denied, since the want of


health, which consists in the proper balance of all the bodily


forces of the man, is a weakness in the system of these forces, by


which system alone we can estimate absolute health.






III. Of the Reason for conceiving an End which is also a Duty



8






An end is an object of the free elective will, the idea of which


determines this will to an action by which the object is produced.


Accordingly every action has its end, and as no one can have an end


without himself making the object of his elective will his end,


hence to have some end of actions is an act of the freedom of the


agent, not an affect of physical nature. Now, since this act which


determines an end is a practical principle which commands not the


means (therefore not conditionally) but the end itself (therefore


unconditionally), hence it is a categorical imperative of pure


practical reason and one, therefore, which combines a concept of


duty with that of an end in general.




Now there must be such an end and a categorical imperative


corresponding to it. For since there are free actions, there must also


be ends to which as an object those actions are directed. Amongst


these ends there must also be some which are at the same time (that


is, by their very notion) duties. For if there were none such, then


since no actions can be without an end, all ends which practical


reason might have would be valid only as means to other ends, and a


categorical imperative would be impossible; a supposition which


destroys all moral philosophy.




Here, therefore, we treat not of ends which man actually makes to


himself in accordance with the sensible impulses of his nature, but of


objects of the free elective will under its own laws- objects which he


ought to make his end. We may call the former technical


(subjective), properly pragmatical, including the rules of prudence in


the choice of its ends; but the latter we must call the moral


(objective) doctrine of ends. This distinction is, however,


superfluous here, since moral philosophy already by its very notion is


clearly separated from the doctrine of physical nature (in the present


instance, anthropology). The latter resting on empirical principles,


whereas the moral doctrine of ends which treats of duties rests on


principles given a priori in pure practical reason.






IV


. What are the Ends which are also Duties?





They are: A. OUR OWN PERFECTION, B. HAPPINESS OF OTHERS.




We cannot invert these and make on one side our own happiness, and


on the other the perfection of others, ends which should be in


themselves duties for the same person.




For one's own happiness is, no doubt, an end that all men have (by


virtue of the impulse of their nature), but this end cannot without


contradiction be regarded as a duty. What a man of himself


inevitably wills does not come under the notion of duty, for this is a


9




constraint to an end reluctantly adopted. It is, therefore, a


contradiction to say that a man is in duty bound to advance his own


happiness with all his power.




It is likewise a contradiction to make the perfection of another


my end, and to regard myself as in duty bound to promote it. For it is


just in this that the perfection of another man as a person


consists, namely, that he is able of himself to set before him his own


end according to his own notions of duty; and it is a contradiction to


require (to make it a duty for me) that I should do something which no


other but himself can do.






V


. Explanation of these two Notions





















A. OUR OWN PERFECTION





The word perfection is liable to many misconceptions. It is


sometimes understood as a notion belonging to transcendental


philosophy; viz., the notion of the totality of the manifold which


taken together constitutes a thing; sometimes, again, it is understood


as belonging to teleology, so that it signifies the correspondence


of the properties of a thing to an end. Perfection in the former sense


might be called quantitative (material), in the latter qualitative


(formal) perfection. The former can be one only, for the whole of what


belongs to the one thing is one. But of the latter there may be


several in one thing; and it is of the latter property that we here


treat.




When it is said of the perfection that belongs to man generally


(properly speaking, to humanity), that it is in itself a duty to


make this our end, it must be placed in that which may be the effect


of one's deed, not in that which is merely an endowment for which we


have to thank nature; for otherwise it would not be duty.


Consequently, it can be nothing else than the cultivation of one's


power (or natural capacity) and also of one's will (moral disposition)


to satisfy the requirement of duty in general. The supreme element


in the former (the power) is the understanding, it being the faculty


of concepts, and, therefore, also of those concepts which refer to


duty. First it is his duty to labour to raise himself out of the


rudeness of his nature, out of his animal nature more and more to


humanity, by which alone he is capable of setting before him ends to


supply the defects of his ignorance by instruction, and to correct his


errors; he is not merely counselled to do this by reason as


technically practical, with a view to his purposes of other kinds


(as art), but reason, as morally practical, absolutely commands him to


10




do it, and makes this end his duty, in order that he may be worthy


of the humanity that dwells in him. Secondly, to carry the cultivation


of his will up to the purest virtuous disposition, that, namely, in


which the law is also the spring of his dutiful actions, and to obey


it from duty, for this is internal morally practical perfection.


This is called the moral sense (as it were a special sense, sensus


moralis), because it is a feeling of the effect which the


legislative will within himself exercises on the faculty of acting


accordingly. This is, indeed, often misused fanatically, as though


(like the genius of Socrates) it preceded reason, or even could


dispense with judgement of reason; but still it is a moral perfection,


making every special end, which is also a duty, one's own end.




















B. HAPPINESS OF OTHERS





It is inevitable for human nature that a should wish and seek for


happiness, that is, satisfaction with his condition, with certainty of


the continuance of this satisfaction. But for this very reason it is


not an end that is also a duty. Some writers still make a


distinction between moral and physical happiness (the former


consisting in satisfaction with one's person and moral behaviour, that


is, with what one does; the other in satisfaction with that which


nature confers, consequently with what one enjoys as a foreign


gift). Without at present censuring the misuse of the word (which even


involves a contradiction), it must be observed that the feeling of the


former belongs solely to the preceding head, namely, perfection. For


he who is to feel himself happy in the mere consciousness of his


uprightness already possesses that perfection which in the previous


section was defined as that end which is also duty.




If happiness, then, is in question, which it is to be my duty to


promote as my end, it must be the happiness of other men whose


(permitted) end I hereby make also mine. It still remains left to


themselves to decide what they shall reckon as belonging to their


happiness; only that it is in my power to decline many things which


they so reckon, but which I do not so regard, supposing that they have


no right to demand it from me as their own. A plausible objection


often advanced against the division of duties above adopted consists


in setting over against that end a supposed obligation to study my own


(physical) happiness, and thus making this, which is my natural and


merely subjective end, my duty (and objective end). This requires to


be cleared up.




Adversity, pain, and want are great temptations to transgression


of one's duty; accordingly it would seem that strength, health, a


competence, and welfare generally, which are opposed to that


11




influence, may also be regarded as ends that are also duties; that is,


that it is a duty to promote our own happiness not merely to make that


of others our end. But in that case the end is not happiness but the


morality of the agent; and happiness is only the means of removing the


hindrances to morality; permitted means, since no one bas a right to


demand from me the sacrifice of my not immoral ends. It is not


directly a duty to seek a competence for one's self; but indirectly it


may be so; namely, in order to guard against poverty which is a


great temptation to vice. But then it is not my happiness but my


morality, to maintain which in its integrity is at once my end and


my duty.






VI. Ethics does not supply Laws for Actions (which is done by








Jurisprudence), but only for the Maxims of Action





The notion of duty stands in immediate relation to a law (even


though I abstract from every end which is the matter of the law); as


is shown by the formal principle of duty in the categorical


imperative:


universal law.


own will, not of will in general, which might be that of others; for


in the latter case it would give rise to a judicial duty which does


not belong to the domain of ethics. In ethics, maxims are regarded


as those subjective laws which merely have the specific character of


universal legislation, which is only a negative principle (not to


contradict a law in general). How, then, can there be further a law


for the maxims of actions?




It is the notion of an end which is also a duty, a notion peculiar


to ethics, that alone is the foundation of a law for the maxims of


actions; by making the subjective end (that which every one has)


subordinate to the objective end (that which every one ought to make


his own). The imperative:


g., the happiness of others)


will (an object). Now since no free action is possible, without the


agent having in view in it some end (as matter of his elective


will), it follows that, if there is an end which is also a duty, the


maxims of actions which are means to ends must contain only the


condition of fitness for a possible universal legislation: on the


other hand, the end which is also a duty can make it a law that we


should have such a maxim, whilst for the maxim itself the


possibility of agreeing with a universal legislation is sufficient.




For maxims of actions may be arbitrary, and are only limited by


the condition of fitness for a universal legislation, which is the


12




formal principle of actions. But a law abolishes the arbitrary


character of actions, and is by this distinguished from recommendation


(in which one only desires to know the best means to an end).






VII. Ethical Duties are of indeterminate, Juridical Duties of






















strict, Obligation





This proposition is a consequence of the foregoing; for if the law


can only command the maxim of the actions, not the actions themselves,


this is a sign that it leaves in the observance of it a latitude


(latitudo) for the elective will; that is, it cannot definitely assign


how and how much we should do by the action towards the end which is


also duty. But by an indeterminate duty is not meant a permission to


make exceptions from the maxim of the actions, but only the permission


to limit one maxim of duty by another (e. g., the general love of


our neighbour by the love of parents); and this in fact enlarges the


field for the practice of virtue. The more indeterminate the duty, and


the more imperfect accordingly the obligation of the man to the


action, and the closer he nevertheless brings this maxim of


obedience thereto (in his own mind) to the strict duty (of justice),


so much the more perfect is his virtuous action.




Hence it is only imperfect duties that are duties of virtue. The


fulfilment of them is merit (meritum) = + a; but their transgression


is not necessarily demerit (demeritum) = - a, but only moral unworth


= o, unless the agent made it a principle not to conform to those


duties. The strength of purpose in the former case is alone properly


called virtue [Tugend] (virtus); the weakness in the latter case is


not vice (vitium), but rather only lack of virtue [Untugend], a want


of moral strength (defectus moralis). (As the word Tugend is derived


from taugen [to be good for something], Untugend by its etymology


signifies good for nothing.) Every action contrary to duty is called


transgression (peccatum). Deliberate transgression which has become


a principle is what properly constitutes what is called vice (vitium).




Although the conformity of actions to justice (i.e., to be an


upright man) is nothing meritorious, yet the conformity of the maxim


of such actions regarded as duties, that is, reverence for justice


is meritorious. For by this the man makes the right of humanity or


of men his own end, and thereby enlarges his notion of duty beyond


that of indebtedness (officium debiti), since although another man


by virtue of his rights can demand that my actions shall conform to


the law, he cannot demand that the law shall also contain the spring


of these actions. The same thing is true of the general ethical


command,


13




firmly in one's mind and to quicken it is, as in the former case,


meritorious, because it goes beyond the law of duty in actions and


makes the law in itself the spring.




But just for or reason, those duties also must be reckoned as of


indeterminate obligation, in respect of which there exists a


subjective principle which ethically rewards them; or to bring them as


near as possible to the notion of a strict obligation, a principle


of susceptibility of this reward according to the law of virtue;


namely, a moral pleasure which goes beyond mere satisfaction with


oneself (which may be merely negative), and of which it is proudly


said that in this consciousness virtue is its own reward.




When this merit is a merit of the man in respect of other men of


promoting their natural ends, which are recognized as such by all


men (making their happiness his own), we might call it the sweet


merit, the consciousness of which creates a moral enjoyment in which


men are by sympathy inclined to revel; whereas the bitter merit of


promoting the true welfare of other men, even though they should not


recognize it as such (in the case of the unthankful and ungrateful),


has commonly no such reaction, but only produces a satisfaction with


one's self, although in the latter case this would be even greater.






VIII. Exposition of the Duties of Virtue as Intermediate Duties





(1) OUR OWN PERFECTION as an end which is also a duty




(a) Physical perfection; that is, cultivation of all our faculties


generally for the promotion of the ends set before us by reason.


That this is a duty, and therefore an end in itself, and that the


effort to effect this even without regard to the advantage that it


secures us, is based, not on a conditional (pragmatic), but an


unconditional (moral) imperative, may be seen from the following


consideration. The power of proposing to ourselves an end is the


characteristic of humanity (as distinguished from the brutes). With


the end of humanity in our own person is therefore combined the


rational will, and consequently the duty of deserving well of humanity


by culture generally, by acquiring or advancing the power to carry out


all sorts of possible ends, so far as this power is to be found in


man; that is, it is a duty to cultivate the crude capacities of our


nature, since it is by that cultivation that the animal is raised to


man, therefore it is a duty in itself.




This duty, however, is merely ethical, that is, of indeterminate


obligation. No principle of reason prescribes how far one must go in


this effort (in enlarging or correcting his faculty of


understanding, that is, in acquisition of knowledge or technical


14


-


-


-


-


-


-


-


-



本文更新与2021-02-11 20:57,由作者提供,不代表本网站立场,转载请注明出处:https://www.bjmy2z.cn/gaokao/638895.html

METAPHYSICAL ELEMENTS OF ETHICS的相关文章