关键词不能为空

当前您在: 主页 > 英语 >

What_is_life_(生命是什么)_by_薛定谔

作者:高考题库网
来源:https://www.bjmy2z.cn/gaokao
2021-02-28 19:52
tags:

-

2021年2月28日发(作者:candle)


WHAT IS LIFE?




ERWIN SCHRODINGER




First published 1944






What is life? The Physical Aspect of the Living



Cell.



Based on lectures delivered under the auspices of



the Dublin Institute for Advanced Studies at



Trinity College, Dublin, in February 1943.



To the memory of My Parents






Preface




A scientist is supposed to have a complete and



thorough I of knowledge, at first hand, of some



subjects and, therefore, is usually expected not to



write on any topic of which he is not a life,



master. This is regarded as a matter of noblesse



oblige. For the present purpose I beg to renounce



the noblesse, if any, and to be the freed of the



ensuing obligation. My excuse is as follows: We



have inherited from our forefathers the keen



longing for unified, all-embracing knowledge.



The very name given to the highest institutions



of learning reminds us, that from antiquity to and



throughout many centuries the universal aspect



has been the only one to be given full credit. But



the spread, both in and width and depth, of the



multifarious branches of knowledge by during



the last hundred odd years has confronted us



with a queer dilemma. We feel clearly that we



are only now beginning to acquire reliable



material for welding together the sum total of all



that is known into a whole; but, on the other



hand, it has become next to impossible for a



single mind fully to command more than a small



specialized portion of it. I can see no other



escape from this dilemma (lest our true who aim



be lost for ever) than that some of us should



venture to embark on a synthesis of facts and



theories, albeit with second-hand and incomplete



knowledge of some of them -and at the risk of



making fools of ourselves. So much for my



apology. The difficulties of language are not




negligible. One's native speech is a closely fitting



garment, and one never feels quite at ease when



it is not immediately available and has to be



replaced by another. My thanks are due to Dr



Inkster (Trinity College, Dublin), to Dr Padraig



Browne (St Patrick's College, Maynooth) and,



last but not least, to Mr S. C. Roberts. They were



put to great trouble to fit the new garment on me



and to even greater trouble by my occasional



reluctance to give up some 'original' fashion of



my own. Should some of it have survived the



mitigating tendency of my friends, it is to be put



at my door, not at theirs. The head-lines of the



numerous sections were originally intended to be



marginal summaries, and the text of every



chapter should be read in continuo. E.S.




Dublin September 1944






Homo liber nulla de re minus quam de morte



cogitat; et ejus sapientia non mortis sed vitae



meditatio est. SPINOZA'S Ethics, Pt IV, Prop.



67






(There is nothing over which a free man ponders



less than death; his wisdom is, to meditate not on



death but on life.)






CHAPTER 1



The Classical Physicist's Approach to the Subject





This little book arose from a course of public



lectures, delivered by a theoretical physicist to an



audience of about four hundred which did not



substantially dwindle, though warned at the



outset that the subject-matter was a difficult one



and that the lectures could not be termed popular,



even though the physicist’s most dreaded



weapon, mathematical deduction, would hardly



be utilized. The reason for this was not that the



subject was simple enough to be explained



without mathematics, but rather that it was much



too involved to be fully accessible to



mathematics. Another feature which at least



1


induced a semblance of popularity was the



lecturer's intention to make clear the fundamental



idea, which hovers between biology and physics,



to both the physicist and the biologist. For



actually, in spite of the variety of topics involved,



the whole enterprise is intended to convey one



idea only -one small comment on a large and



important question. In order not to lose our way,



it may be useful to outline the plan very briefly



in advance. The large and important and very



much discussed question is: How can the events



in space and time which take place within the



spatial boundary of a living organism be



accounted for by physics and chemistry? The



preliminary answer which this little book will



endeavor to expound and establish can be



summarized as follows: The obvious inability of



present-day physics and chemistry to account for



such events is no reason at all for doubting that



they can be accounted for by those sciences.






STA


TISTICAL PHYSICS. THE



FUNDAMENTAL W DIFFERENCE IN



STRUCTURE




That would be a very trivial remark if it were



meant


only


to


stimulate


the


hope


of


achieving


in


the


future what has not been achieved in the past.



But the meaning is very much more positive, viz.



that the inability, up to the present moment, is



amply accounted for. Today, thanks to the



ingenious work of biologists, mainly of



geneticists, during the last thirty or forty years,



enough is known about the actual material



structure of organisms and about their



functioning to state that, and to tell precisely



why present-day physics and chemistry could not



possibly account for what happens in space and



time within a living organism. The arrangements



of the atoms in the most vital parts of an



organism and the interplay of these arrangements



differ in a fundamental way from all those



arrangements of atoms which physicists and



chemists have hitherto made the object of their



experimental and theoretical research. Yet the



difference which I have just termed fundamental



is of such a kind that it might easily appear slight



to anyone except a physicist who is thoroughly



imbued with the knowledge that the laws of



physics and chemistry are statistical throughout.



For it is in relation to the statistical point of view



that the structure of the vital parts of living



organisms differs so entirely from that of any



piece of matter that we physicists and chemists



have ever handled physically in our laboratories



or mentally at our writing desks. It is well-nigh



unthinkable that the laws and regularities thus



discovered should happen to apply immediately



to the behaviour of systems which do not exhibit



the structure on which those laws and regularities



are based. The non-physicist cannot be expected



even to grasp let alone to appreciate the



relevance of the difference in ‘statistical



struc


ture’ stated in terms so abstract as I have



just used. To give the statement life and colour,



let me anticipate what will be explained in much



more detail later, namely, that the most essential



part of a living cell-the chromosome fibre may



suitably be called an aperiodic crystal. In physics



we have dealt hitherto only with periodic crystals.



To a humble physicist's mind, these are very



interesting and complicated objects; they



constitute one of the most fascinating



and complex material structures by which



inanimate nature puzzles his wits. Yet, compared



with the aperiodic crystal, they are rather plain



and dull. The difference in structure is of the



same kind as that between an ordinary wallpaper



in which the same pattern is repeated again and



again in regular periodicity and a masterpiece of



embroidery, say a Raphael tapestry, which shows



no dull repetition, but an elaborate, coherent,



meaningful design traced by the great master. In



calling the periodic crystal one of the most



complex objects of his research, I had in mind



the physicist proper. Organic chemistry, indeed,



in investigating more and more complicated




2


molecules, has come very much nearer to that



'aperiodic crystal' which, in my opinion, is the



material carrier of life. And therefore it is small



wonder that the organic chemist has already



made large and important contributions to the



problem of life, whereas the physicist has made



next to none.






THE NAIVE PHYSICIST'S APPROACH TO



THE SUBJECT




After having thus indicated very briefly the



general idea -or rather the ultimate scope -of our



investigation, let me describe the line of attack. I


propose to develop first what you might call 'a



naive physicist's ideas about organisms', that is,



the ideas which might arise in the mind of a



physicist who, after having learnt his physics and,


more especially, the statistical foundation of his



science, begins to think about organisms and



about the way they behave and function and who


comes to ask himself conscientiously whether he,


from what he has learnt, from the point of view



of his comparatively simple and clear and



humble science, can make any relevant



contributions to the question. It will turn out that


he can. The next step must be to f compare his



theoretical anticipations with the biological facts.


It will then turn out that -though on the whole his


ideas seem quite sensible -they need to be



appreciably amended. In this way we shall



gradually approach the correct view -or, to put it



more modestly, the one that I propose as the



correct one. Even if I should be right in this, I do


not know whether my way of approach is really



the best and simplest. But, in short, it was mine.



The 'naive physicist' was myself. And I could not


find any better or clearer way towards the goal



than my own crooked one.






WHY ARE THE ATOMS SO SMALL?




A good method of developing 'the naive



physicist's ideas' is to start from the odd, almost



ludicrous, question: Why are atoms so small? To



begin with, they are very small indeed. Every



little piece of matter handled in everyday life



contains an enormous number of them. Many



examples have been devised to bring this fact



home to an audience, none of them more



impressive than the one used by Lord Kelvin:



Suppose that you could mark the molecules in a



glass of water; then pour the contents of the glass



into


the


ocean


and


stir


the


latter


thoroughly


so


as


to


distribute the marked molecules uniformly



throughout the seven seas; if then you took a



glass of water anywhere out of the ocean, you



would find in it about a hundred of your marked



molecules. The actual sizes of atoms lie between



about 1/5000 and 1/2000 the wave-length of



yellow light. The comparison is significant,



because the wave-length roughly indicates the



dimensions of the smallest grain still



recognizable in the microscope. Thus it will be



seen that such a grain still contains thousands of



millions of atoms. Now, why are atoms so



small? Clearly, the question is an evasion. For it



is not really aimed at the size of the atoms. It is



concerned with the size of organisms, more



particularly with the size of our own corporeal



selves. Indeed, the atom is small, when referred



to our civic unit of length, say the yard or the



metre. In atomic physics one is accustomed to



use the so-called Angstrom (abbr. A), which is



the 10lOth part of a metre, or in decimal notation



0. metre. Atomic diameters range



between 1 and 2A. Now those civic units (in



relation to which the atoms are so small) are



closely related to the size of our bodies. There is



a story tracing the yard back to the humour of an



English king whom his councillors asked what



unit to adopt -and he stretched out his arm



sideways and said: 'Take the distance from the



middle of my chest to my fingertips, that will do



all right.' True or not, the story is significant for



our purpose. The king would naturally I indicate



a length comparable with that of his own body,



knowing that anything else would be very



3












inconvenient. With all his predilection for the



Angstrom unit, the physicist prefers to be told



that his new suit will require six and a half yards



of tweed -rather than sixty-five thousand



millions of Angstroms of tweed. It thus being



settled that our question really aims at the ratio



of two lengths -that of our body and that of the



atom - with an incontestable priority of



independent existence on the side of the atom,



the question truly reads: Why must our bodies be



so large compared with the atom? I can imagine



that many a keen student of physics or chemistry



may have deplored the fact that everyone of our



sense organs, forming a more or less substantial



part of our body and hence (in view of the



magnitude of the said ratio) being itself



composed of innumerable atoms, is much too



coarse to be affected by the impact of a single



atom. We cannot see or feel or hear the single



atoms. Our hypotheses with regard to them differ


widely from the immediate findings of our gross



sense organs and cannot be put to the test of



direct inspection. Must that be so? Is there an



intrinsic reason for it? Can we trace back this



state of affairs to some kind of first principle, in



order to ascertain and to understand why nothing



else is compatible with the very laws of



Nature? Now this, for once, is a problem which



the physicist is able to clear up completely. The



answer to all the queries is in the affirmative.






THE WORKING OF AN ORGANISM



REQUIRES EXACT PHYSICAL LAWS



If it were not so, if we were organisms so



sensitive that a single atom, or even a few atoms,



could make a perceptible impression on our



senses -Heavens, what would life be like! To



stress one point: an organism of that kind would



most certainly not be capable of developing the



kind of orderly thought which, after passing



through a long sequence of earlier stages,



ultimately results in forming, among many other



ideas, the idea of an atom. Even though we select



this one point, the following considerations



would essentially apply also to the functioning of



organs other than the brain and the sensorial



system. Nevertheless, the one and only thing of



paramount interest to us in ourselves is, that we



feel and think and perceive. To the physiological



process which is responsible for thought and



sense all the others play an auxiliary part, at least



from the human point of view, if not from that of



purely objective biology. Moreover, it will



greatly facilitate our task to choose for



investigation the process which is closely



accompanied by subjective events, even though



we are ignorant of the true nature of this close



parallelism. Indeed, in my view, it lies outside



the range of natural science and very probably of



human understanding altogether. We are thus



faced with the following question: Why should



an organ like our brain, with the sensorial system



attached to it, of necessity consist of an



enormous number of atoms, in order that its



physically changing state should be in close and



intimate correspondence with a highly developed



thought? On what grounds is the latter task of the



said organ incompatible with being, as a whole



or in some of its peripheral parts which interact



directly with the environment, a mechanism



sufficiently refined and sensitive to respond to



and register the impact of a single atom from



outside? The reason for this is, that what we call



thought (1) is itself an orderly thing, and (2) can



only be applied to material, i.e. to perceptions or



experiences, which have a certain degree of



orderliness. This has two consequences. First, a



physical


organization,


to


be


in


close


correspondence


with thought (as my brain is



with my thought) must be a very well-ordered



organization, and that means that the events that



happen within it must obey strict physical laws,



at least to a very high degree of accuracy.



Secondly, the physical impressions made upon



that physically well-organized system by other



bodies from outside, obviously correspond to the



4




perception and experience of the corresponding



thought, forming its material, as I have called it.



Therefore, the physical interactions between our



system and others must, as a rule, themselves



possess a certain degree of physical orderliness,



that is to say, they too must obey strict physical



laws to a certain degree of accuracy.






PHYSICAL LAWS REST ON ATOMIC



STA


TISTICS AND ARE THEREFORE ONL


Y



APPROXIMATE




And why could all this not be fulfilled in the case


of an organism composed of a moderate number



of atoms only and sensitive already to the impact


of one or a few atoms only? Because we know



all atoms to perform all the time a completely



disorderly heat motion, which, so to speak,



opposes itself to their orderly behaviour and does


not allow the events that happen between a small


number of atoms to enrol themselves according



to any recognizable laws. Only in the co-


operation of an enormously large number of



atoms do statistical laws begin to operate and



control the behaviour of these assemblies with an


accuracy increasing as the number of atoms



involved increases. It is in that way that the



events acquire truly orderly features. All the



physical and chemical laws that are known to



play an important part in the life of organisms



are of this statistical kind; any other kind of



lawfulness and orderliness that one might think



of is being perpetually disturbed and made



inoperative by the unceasing heat motion of the



atoms.






THEIR PRECISION IS BASED ON THE



LARGE OF NUMBER OF ATOMS



INTERVENING



FIRST EXAMPLE (PARAMAGNETISM)




Let me try to illustrate this by a few examples,



picked somewhat at random out of thousands,



and possibly not just the best ones to appeal to a



reader who is learning for the first time about




this condition of things -a condition which in



modern physics and chemistry is as fundamental



as, say, the fact that organisms are composed of



cells is in biology, or as Newton's Law in



astronomy, or even as the series of integers, 1, 2,



3, 4, 5, ...in mathematics. An entire newcomer



should not expect to obtain from the following



few pages a full understanding and appreciation



of the subject, which is associated with the



illustrious names of Ludwig Boltzmann and



Willard Gibbs and treated in textbooks under the



name of 'statistical thermodynamics'. If you fill



an oblong quartz tube with oxygen gas and put it



into a magnetic field, you find that the gas is



magnetized. The magnetization is due to the fact



that the oxygen molecules are little magnets and



tend to orientate themselves parallel to the field,



like a compass needle. But you must not think



that they actually all turn parallel. For if you



double the field, you get double the



magnetization in your oxygen body, and that



proportionality goes on to extremely high field



strengths, the magnetization increasing at the rate


of the field you apply. This is a particularly clear



example of a purely statistical law. The



orientation the field tends to produce is



continually counteracted by the heat motion,



which works for random orientation. The effect



of this striving is, actually, only a small



preference for acute over obtuse angles between



the dipole axes and the field. Though the single



atoms change their orientation incessantly, they



produce on the average (owing to their enormous



number) a constant small preponderance of



orientation in the direction of the field and



proportional to it. This ingenious explanation is



due to the French physicist P. Langevin. It can



be checked in the following way. If the observed



weak magnetization is really the outcome of rival


tendencies, namely, the magnetic field, which



aims at combing all the molecules parallel, and



the heat motion, which makes for random



orientation, then it ought to be possible to



5









increase the magnetization by weakening the



heat motion, that is to say, by lowering the



temperature, instead of reinforcing the field. That



impact of one single molecule of those which



hammer their surface in perpetual impacts. They



are thus knocked about and can only on the



is confirmed by experiment, which gives the



magnetization inversely proportional to the



absolute temperature, in quantitative agreement



with theory (Curie's law). Modern equipment



even enables us, by lowering the temperature, to



reduce the heat motion to such insignificance



that the orientating tendency of the magnetic



field can assert itself, if not completely, at least



sufficiently to produce a substantial fraction of



'complete magnetization'. In this case we no



longer expect that double the field strength will



double the magnetization, but that the latter will



increase less and less with increasing field,



approaching what is called 'saturation'. This



expectation


too


is


quantitatively


confirmed


experiment. Notice that this behaviour entirely



depends on the large numbers of molecules



which co-operate in producing the observable



magnetization. Otherwise, the latter would not be


an constant at all, but would, by fluctuating quite



irregularly of from one second to the next, bear



witness to the vicissitudes of pe the contest



between heat motion and field.






SECOND EXAMPLE (BROWNIAN



MOVEMENT, DIFFUSION)




If you fill the lower part of a closed glass vessel



with fog, pt consisting of minute droplets, you



will find that the upper or boundary of the fog



gradually sinks, with a well-defined velocity,



determined by the viscosity of the air and the



size and the specific gravity of the droplets. But



if you look at one of the droplets under the



microscope you find that it does not permanently



sink with constant velocity, but performs a very



irregular movement, the so-called Brownian



movement, which corresponds to a regular



sinking only on the average. Now these droplets



are not atoms, but they are sufficiently small and



light to be not entirely insusceptible to the




average follow the influence of gravity. This



example shows what funny and disorderly



experience we should have if our senses were



susceptible to the impact of a few molecules only.



There are bacteria and other organisms so small



that they are strongly affected by this



phenomenon. Their movements are determined



by the thermic whims of the surrounding



medium; they have no choice. If they had some



locomotion of their own they might nevertheless



succeed in on getting from one place to another -


but with some difficulty, since the heat motion



tosses them like a small boat in a rough sea. A



phenomenon very much akin to Brownian



by


movement is that of diffusion. Imagine a vessel



filled with a fluid, say water, with a small



amount of some coloured substance dissolved in



it, say potassium permanganate, not in uniform



concentration, but rather as in Fig. 4, where the



dots indicate the molecules of the dissolved



substance (permanganate) and the concentration



diminishes from left to right. If you leave this



system alone a very slow process of 'diffusion'



sets in, the at permanganate spreading in the



direction from left to right, that is, from the



places of higher concentration towards the places



of lower concentration, until it is equally



distributed of through the water. The remarkable



thing about this rather simple and apparently not



particularly interesting process is that it is in no



way due, as one might think, to any tendency or



force driving the permanganate molecules away



from the crowded region to the less crowded one,



like the population of a country spreading to



those parts where there is more elbow-room.



Nothing of the sort happens with our



permanganate molecules. Every one of them



behaves quite independently of all the others,



which it very seldom meets. Everyone of them,



whether in a crowded region or in an empty one,



6



suffers the same fate of being continually



knocked about by the impacts of the water



molecules and thereby gradually moving on in



an unpredictable direction -sometimes towards



the higher, sometimes towards the lower,



concentrations, sometimes obliquely. The kind



of motion it performs has often been compared



with that of a blindfolded person on a large



surface imbued with a certain desire of 'walking',



but without any preference for any particular



direction, and so changing his line



continuously. That this random walk of the



permanganate molecules, the same for all of



them, should yet produce a regular flow towards



the smaller concentration and ultimately make



for uniformity of distribution, is at first sight



perplexing -but only at first sight. If you



contemplate in Fig. 4 thin slices of



approximately constant concentration, the



permanganate molecules which in a given



moment are contained in a particular slice will,



by their random walk, it is true, be carried with



equal probability to the right or to the left. But



precisely in consequence of this, a plane



separating two neighbouring slices will be



crossed by more molecules coming from the left



than in the opposite direction, simply because to



the left there are more molecules engaged in



random walk than there are to the right. And as



long as that is so the balance will show up as a



regular flow from left to right, until a uniform



distribution is reached. When these



considerations are translated into mathematical



language the exact law of diffusion is reached in



the form of a partial differential equation






§


p/§


t= DV2


P






which I shall not trouble the reader by explaining,


though its meaning in ordinary language is again



simple enough. The reason for mentioning the



stern 'mathematically exact' law here, is to




emphasize that its physical exactitude must



nevertheless


be


challenged


in


every


particular


application. Being based on pure chance, its



validity is only approximate. If it is, as a rule, a



very good approximation, that is only due to the



enormous number of molecules that co- operate



in the phenomenon. The smaller their number,



the larger the quite haphazard deviations we



must expect and they can be observed under



favourable circumstances.






THIRD EXAMPLE (LIMITS OF ACCURACY



OF MEASURING)



The last example we shall give is closely akin to



the second c one, but has a particular interest. A



light body, suspended by a long thin fibre in



equilibrium orientation, is often used by



physicists to measure weak forces which deflect



it from that position of equilibrium, electric,



magnetic or gravitational forces being applied so



as to twist it around the vertical axis. (The light



body must, of course, be chosen appropriately



for ! the particular purpose.) The continued effort



to improve the accuracy of this very commonly



used device of a 'torsional balance', has



encountered a curious limit, most interesting in



itself. In choosing lighter and lighter bodies and



thinner and longer fibres -to make the balance



susceptible to weaker and weaker forces -the



limit was reached when the suspended body



became noticeably susceptible to the impacts of



the heat motion of the surrounding molecules



and began to perform an incessant, irregular



'dance' about its equilibrium position, much like



the trembling of the droplet in the second



example. Though this behaviour sets no absolute



limit to the accuracy of measurements obtained



with the balance, it sets a practical one. The



uncontrollable effect of the heat motion



competes with the effect of the force to be



measured and makes the t' law single deflection



observed insignificant. You have to multiply



never- observations, in order to eliminate the



7



effect of the Brownian Being movement of your



instrument. This example is, I think, particularly



illuminating in our present investigation. For our



to the organs of sense, after all, are a kind of



instrument. We can see in the how useless they



would be if they became too sensitive.






THE



/n RULE




So much for examples, for the present. I will



merely add that there is not one law of physics or



chemistry, of those that are relevant within an



organism or in its interactions with its



environment, that I might not choose as an



example. The second detailed explanation might



be more complicated, but the salient point would



always be the same and thus the description



would become monotonous. But I should like to



add one very important quantitative statement



concerning the degree of inaccuracy to be



expected in any physical law, the so-called /n



law. I will first illustrate it by a simple example



and then generalize it. If I tell you that a certain



gas under certain conditions of pressure and



temperature has a certain density, and if I



expressed this by saying that within a certain



volume (of a size relevant for some experiment)



there are under these conditions just n molecules



of the gas, then you might be sure that if you



could test my statement in a particular moment



of time, you would find it inaccurate, the



departure being of the order of



/n. Hence if the



number n = 100, you would find a departure of



about 10, thus relative error = 10%. But n = 1



million, you would be likely to find a departure



of about 1,000, thus relative error = 110%. Now,



roughly speaking, this statistical law is quite



general. The laws of physics and physical



chemistry are inaccurate within a probable



relative error of the order of 1/ /Vn, where n is



the number of molecules that co-operate to bring



about that law -to produce its validity within



such regions of space or time (or both) that



matter, for some considerations or for some




particular experiment. You see from this again



that an organism must have a comparatively



gross structure in order to enjoy the benefit of



fairly accurate laws, both for its internal life and



for its , interplay with the external world. For



otherwise the number of co-operating particles



would be too small, the 'law' too inaccurate. The



particularly exigent demand is the square root.



For though n is a reasonably large



number, an accuracy of Just 1in 1,000 is not



overwhelmingly good, If a thing claims the



dignity of being a 'Law of Nature.





CHAPTER 2




The Hereditary Mechanism






THE CLASSICAL PHYSICIST'S



EXPECTATION, FAR FROM BEING



TRIVIAL, IS WRONG




Thus we have come to the conclusion that an



organism and all the biologically relevant



processes that it experiences must have an



extremely 'many-atomic' structure and must be



safeguarded against haphazard, 'single- atomic'



events attaining too great importance. That, the



'naive physicist' tells us, is essential, so that the



organism may, so to speak, have sufficiently



accurate physical laws on which to draw for setting up


its marvellously regular and well-


ordered working. How do these conclusions,



reached, biologically speaking, a priori (that is,



from the purely physical point of view), fit



in with actual biological facts? At first sight one



is inclined to think that the conclusions are little



more than trivial. A biologist of, say, thirty years



ago might have said that, although it was quite



suitable for a popular lecturer to emphasize the



importance, in the organism as elsewhere, of



statistical physics, the point was, in fact, rather a



familiar truism. For, naturally, not only the body



of an adult individual of any higher species, but



every single cell composing it contains a



'cosmical' number of single atoms of every kind.



8


And every particular physiological process that



we observe, either within the cell or in its



interaction with the cell environment, appears -or



appeared thirty years ago -to involve such



enormous numbers of single atoms and single



atomic processes that all the relevant laws of



physics and physical chemistry would be



safeguarded even under the very exacting



demands of statistical physics in respect of large



numbers; this demand illustrated just now by the



/n rule. Today, we know that this opinion would



have been a mistake. As we shall presently see,



incredibly small groups of atoms, much too



small to display exact statistical laws, do play a



dominating role in the very orderly and lawful



events within a living organism. They have



control of the observable large-scale features



which the organism acquires in the course of its



development, they determine important



characteristics of its functioning; and in all this



very sharp and very strict me biological laws are



displayed. I must begin with giving a brief



summary of the situation in biology, more



especially in genetics -in other words, I have to



summarize the present state of knowledge in a



subject of which I am not a master. This cannot



be helped and I apologize, particularly to any



biologist, for the dilettante character of my



summary. On the other hand, I beg leave to put



the prevailing ideas before you more or less



dogmatically. A poor theoretical physicist could



not be expected to produce anything like a



competent survey of the experimental evidence,



which consists of a large number of long and



beautifully interwoven series of breeding



experiments of truly unprecedented ingenuity on



the one hand and of direct observations of the



living cell, conducted with all the refinement of



modern microscopy, on the other.






THE HEREDITARY CODE-SCRIPT



(CHROMOSOMES)




Let me use the word 'pattern' of an organism in




the sense in be which the biologist calls it 'the



four-dimensional pattern', meaning not only the



structure and functioning of that organism in the



adult, or in any other particular stage, but the



whole of its ontogenetic development from the



fertilized egg the cell to the stage of maturity,



when the organism begins to reproduce itself.



Now, this whole four-dimensional pattern is



known to be determined by the structure of that



one cell, the fertilized egg. Moreover, we know



that it is essentially determined by the structure



of only a small part of that cell, its large nucleus.



This nucleus, in the ordinary 'resting state' of the



cell, usually appears as a network of chromatine,



distributed over the cell. But in the vitally



important processes of cell division (mitosis and



meiosis, see below) it is seen to consist of a set



of particles, usually fibre-shaped or rod-like,



called the chromosomes, which number 8 or 12



or, in man, 48. But I ought really to have written



these illustrative numbers as 2 X 4, 2 X 6, ..., 2 X


24, ..., and I ought to have spoken of two sets, in



order to use the expression in the customary



strict meaning of the biologist. For though the



single chromosomes are sometimes clearly



distinguished and individualized by shape and



size, the two sets are almost entirely alike. As we


have shall see in a moment, one set comes from



the mother (egg cell), one from the father



(fertilizing spermatozoon). It is these



chromosomes, or probably only an axial skeleton


fibre of what we actually see under the



microscope as the chromosome, that contain in



some kind of code-script the entire pattern of the



individual's future development and of its



functioning in the mature state. Every complete



set of chromosomes contains the full code; so



there are, as a rule, two copies of the latter in the



fertilized egg cell, which forms the earliest stage



of the future individual. In calling the structure



of the chromosome fibres a code-script we mean



that the all-penetrating mind, once conceived by



Laplace, to which every causal connection lay



9





immediately open, could tell from their structure



whether the egg would develop, under suitable



conditions, into a black cock or into a speckled



hen, into a fly or a maize plant, a rhododendron,



a beetle, a mouse or a woman. To which we may



add, that the appearances of the egg cells are



very often remarkably similar; and even when



they are not, as in the case of the comparatively



gigantic eggs of birds and reptiles, the difference



is


not


been


so


much


the


relevant


structures


as


in


the


nutritive material which in these cases is



added for obvious reasons. But the term




code-script is, of course, too narrow. The



chromosome structures are at the same time



instrumental in bringing about the development



they foreshadow. They are law-code and



executive power -or, to use another simile, they



are architect's plan and builder's craft -in one.





GROWTH OF THE BODY BY CELL



DIVISION (MITOSIS)




How do the chromosomes behave in ontogenesis?



The growth of an organism is effected by



consecutive cell met divisions. Such a cell



division is called mitosis. It is, in the life of a cell,



not such a very frequent event as one might



expect, considering the enormous number of



cells of which our body is composed. In the



beginning the growth is rapid. The egg divides



into two 'daughter cells' which, at the next step,



will produce a generation of four, then of 8, 16,



32, 64, ..., etc. The frequency of division will not



remain exactly the same in all parts of the



growing body, and that will break the regularity



of these numbers. But from their rapid increase



we infer by an easy computation that on the



average as few as 50 or 60 successive divisions



suffice to produce the number of cells in a grown



man -or, say, ten times the number, taking into



account the exchange of cells during lifetime.



Thus, a body cell of mine is, on the average, only



the 50th or 60th 'descendant' of the egg that was I.






IN MITOSIS EVERY CHROMOSOME IS



DUPLICATED



How do the chromosomes behave on mitosis?



They duplicate -both sets, both copies of the



code, duplicate. The process has been intensively



studied under the microscope and is of



paramount interest, but much too involved to



describe here in detail. The salient point is that



each of the two 'daughter cells' gets a dowry of



two further complete sets of chromosomes



exactly similar to those of the parent cell. So all



the body cells are exactly alike as regards their



chromosome treasure. However little we



understand the device we cannot but think that it



must be in some way very relevant to the



functioning of the organism, that every single



cell, even a less important one, should be in



possession of a complete (double) copy of the



code-script. Some time ago we were told in the



newspapers that in his African campaign General



Montgomery made a point of having every



single soldier of his army meticulously informed



of all his designs. If that is true (as it conceivably



might be, considering the high intelligence and



reliability of his troops) it provides an excellent



analogy to our case, in which the corresponding



fact certainly is literally true. The most



surprising fact is the doubleness of the



chromosome set, maintained throughout the



mitotic divisions. That it is the outstanding



feature of the genetic mechanism is most



strikingly revealed by the one and only departure



from the rule, which we have now to discuss.






REDUCTIVE DIVISION (MEIOSIS) AND



FERTILIZATION (SYNGAMY)



Very soon after the development of the



individual has set in, a group of cells is reserved



for producing at a later stage the so-called



gametes, the sperm cells or egg cells, as the case



may be, needed for the reproduction of the



individual in maturity. 'Reserved' means that



they do not serve other purposes in the meantime




10


and suffer many fewer mitotic divisions. The



exceptional or reductive division (called meiosis)



is the one by which eventually, on maturity, the



gametes posed to are produced from these



reserved cells, as a rule only a short time before



syngamy is to take place. In meiosis the double



chromosome set of the parent cell simply



separates into two single sets, one of which goes



to each of the two daughter cells, the gametes. In



other words, the mitotic doubling of the number



of chromosomes does not take place in meiosis,



the number remains constant and thus every



gamete receives only half -that is, only one



complete copy of the code, not two, e.g. in man



only 24:, not 2 X 24: = 4:8. Cells with only one



chromosome set are called haploid (from Greek



α


π

< br>λ


ο


?


χ, single). Thus the gametes are


haploid,



the ordinary body cells diploid (from Greek



Ο


π


λ


?


χ, double). Individuals with three,



four, ...or generally speaking with many



chromosome sets in all their body cells occur



occasionally; the latter are then called triploid,



tetraploid, ..., polyploid. In the act of syngamy



the male gamete (spermatozoon) and the female



gamete (egg), both haploid cells, coalesce to



form the fertilized egg cell, which is thus diploid.



One of its chromosome sets comes from the



mother, one from the father.






HAPLOID INDIVIDUALS




One other point needs rectification. Though not



indispensable for our purpose it is of real interest,



since it shows that actually a fairly complete



code-script of the 'pattern' is contained in every



single set of chromosomes. There are instances



of


meiosis


not


being


followed


shortly


after


by


fertilization, the haploid cell (the 'gamete')



under- going meanwhile numerous mitotic cell



divisions, which result in building up a complete



haploid individual. This is the case in the male



bee, the drone, which is produced



parthenogenetically, that is, from non- fertilized



and therefore haploid eggs of the queen. The



drone has no father! All its body cells are haploid.



If you please, you may call it a grossly



exaggerated spermatozoon; and actually, as



everybody knows, to function as such happens to



be its one and only task in life. However, that is



perhaps a ludicrous point of view. For the case is



not two quite unique. There are families of plants



in which the haploid gamete which is produced



by meiosis and is called a spore in the such cases



falls to the ground and, like a seed, develops into



a the true haploid plant comparable in size with



the diploid.







Fig. 5 is a rough sketch of a moss,



well known in our forests. The leafy lower part is



the haploid plant, called the gametophyte,



because at its upper end it develops sex organs



and gametes, which by mutual fertilization



produce in the ordinary way the diploid plant,



the bare stem with the capsule at the top. This is



called the sporophyte, because it produces, by



meiosis, the spores in the capsule at the top.



When the capsule opens, the spores fall to the



ground and develop into a leafy stem, etc. The



course of events is appropriately called



alternation of generations. You may, if you



choose, look upon the ordinary case, man and the



animals, in the same way. But the 'gametophyte'



is then as a rule a very short-lived, unicellular



generation, spermatozoon or egg cell as the case



may be. Our body corresponds to the sporophyte.



Our 'spores' are the reserved cells from which, by



meiosis, the unicellular generation springs.






THE OUTSTANDING RELEVANCE OF



THE REDUCTIVE DIVISION




The important, the really fateful event in the



process of reproduction of the individual is not



fertilization but meiosis. One set of



chromosomes is from the father, one from the



mother. Neither chance nor destiny can interfere



with that. Every man owes just half of his



inheritance to his mother, half of it to his father.




11


That one or the other strain seems often to



prevail is due to other reasons which we shall



come to later. (Sex itself is, of course, the



simplest instance of such prevalence.). But when



you trace the origin of your inheritance back to



your grandparents, the case is different. Let me



fix attention on my paternal set of chromosomes,



in particular on one of them, say No.5. It is a



faithful replica either of the No.5 my father



received from his father or of the No.5 he had



received from his mother. The issue was decided



by a 50:50 chance in the meiosis taking place in



my father's body in November 1886 and



producing the spermatozoon which a few days



later was to be effective in begetting me. Exactly



the same story could be repeated about



chromosomes Nos. 1, 2, 3, ...,24 of my paternal



set, and mutatis mutandis about every one of my



maternal chromosomes. Moreover, all the 48



issues are fi entirely independent. Even if it were



known that my paternal it chromosome No.5



came from my grandfather Josef Schrodinger,



the No.7 still stands an equal chance of being



either also from him, or from his wife Marie, nee



Bogner.






CROSSING-OVER. LOCA


TION OF



PROPERTIES




But pure chance has been given even a wider



range in mixing the grandparental inheritance in



the offspring than would appear from the



preceding description, in which it has been



tacitly assumed, or even explicitly stated, that a



particular chromosome as a whole was either



from the grandfather or back to from the



grandmother; in other words that the single



chromosomes are passed on undivided. In actual



fact they are not, or on one of not always. Before



being separated in the reductive division, No.5



my say the one in the father's body, any two



'homologous' chromosomes come into close



contact with each other, during chance in which



they sometimes exchange entire portions in the




way illustrated in Fig. 6. By this process, called



'crossing-over', days later two properties situated



in the respective parts of that chromosome will



be separated in the grandchild, who will follow



the grandfather in one of them, the grandmother



in the other one. The act of crossing-over, being



neither very rare nor very issues are frequent, has



provided us with invaluable information



regarding the location of properties in the



chromosomes. For a full account we should have



to draw on conceptions not introduced before the



next chapter (e.g. heterozygosy, dominance, etc.);



but as that would take us beyond the range of



this little book, let me indicate the salient point



right away. If there were no crossing- over, two



properties for which the same chromosome is



responsible would always be passed on in



mixing together, no descendant receiving one of



them without receiving the other as well; but two



properties, due to different it has been



chromosomes,


would


either


stand


a


50:50


chance


of


being separated or they would invariably be



separated -the latter when they were situated in



homologous chromosomes of the same ancestor,



which could never go together. These rules and



chances are interfered with by crossing-over.



Hence the probability of this event can be



ascertained by registering carefully the



percentage composition of the off-spring in



extended breeding experiments, suitably laid out



for at the purpose. In analysing the statistics, one



accepts the suggestive working hypothesis that



the 'linkage' between two properties situated in



the same chromosome, is the less frequently



broken by crossing-over, the nearer they lie to



each other. For then there is less chance of the



point of exchange lying between them, whereas



properties located near the opposite ends of the



chromosomes are separated by every crossing-


over. (Much the same applies to the



recombination of properties located in



homologous chromosomes of the same ancestor.)



In this way one may expect to get from the



12


'statistics of linkage' a sort of 'map of properties'



within every chromosome. These anticipations



have been fully confirmed. In the cases to which



tests have been thoroughly applied (mainly, but



not only, Drosophila) the tested properties



actually divide into as h many separate groups,



with no linkage from group to group, as there are



different chromosomes (four in Drosophila).



Within every group a linear map of properties



can be drawn up which accounts quantitatively



for the degree of linkage it between any two of



that group, so that there is little doubt h that they



actually are located, and located along a line, as



the rod-like shape of the chromosome suggests.



Of course, the scheme of the hereditary



mechanism, as drawn up here, is still rather



empty and colourless, even slightly naive. For



we have not said what exactly we understand by



a property. It seems neither adequate nor



possible to dissect into discrete 'properties' the



pattern of an organism which is essentially a



unity, a 'whole'. Now, what we actually state in



any particular case is, that a pair of ancestors



were different in a certain well- defined respect



(say, one had blue eyes, the other brown), and



that the offspring follows in this respect either



one or the other. What we locate in



the chromosome is the seat of this difference.



(We call it, in technical language, a 'locus', or, if



we think of the hypothetical material structure



underlying it, a 'gene'.) Difference of by property,



to my view, is really the fundamental concept



rather than property itself, notwithstanding the



apparent linguistic out for and logical



contradiction of this statement. The differences



of Its the properties actually are discrete, as will



emerge in the next chapter when we have to



speak of mutations and the dry scheme hitherto



presented will, as I hope, acquire more life each



colour.






MAXIMUM SIZE OF A GENE




We have just introduced the term gene for the




hypothetical same material carrier of a definite



hereditary feature. We must now the stress two



points which will be highly relevant to our every



investigation. The first is the size -or, better, the



maximum size -of such a carrier; in other words,



to how small a volume can we trace the location?



The second point will be the permanence of a



gene, to be inferred from the durability of the



hereditary pattern. As regards the size, there are



two entirely independent estimates, one resting



on genetic evidence (breeding experiments), the



other on cytological evidence (direct microscopic



inspection). The first is, in principle, simple



enough. After having, in the way described



above, located in the chromosome a considerable



number of different (large-scale) features (say of



the Drosophila fly) within a particular one of its



chromosomes, to get the required estimate we



need only divide the measured length of that



chromosome by the number of features and



multiply by the cross-section. For, of course, we



count as different only such features as are



occasionally separated by crossing-over, so that



they cannot be due to the same (microscopic or



molecular) structure. On the other hand, it is



clear that our estimate can only give a maximum



size, because the number of features isolated by



in this genetic analysis is continually increasing



as work goes on. The other estimate, though



based on microscopic inspection, is really far



less direct. Certain cells of Drosophila (namely,



those of its salivary glands) are, for some reason,



enormously enlarged, and so are their



chromosomes. In them you distinguish a



crowded pattern of transverse dark bands across



the fibre. C. D. Darlington has remarked that the



number of these bands (2,000 in the case he uses)



is, though, considerably larger, yet roughly of the



same order of magnitude as the number of genes



located in that chromosome by breeding



experiments. He inclines to regard these bands as



indicating the actual genes (or separations of



genes). Dividing the length of the chromosome,



13


measured in a normal-sized cell by their number



(2,000) he finds the volume of a gene equal to a



cube of edge 300 A. Considering the roughness of the


that what is passed on by the parent to the child



is not just this or that peculiarity, a hooked nose,



short fingers, a tendency to rheumatism,



estimates, we may regard this to be also



the size obtained by the first method.





SMALL NUMBERS



A full discussion of the bearing of statistical



physics on all the facts I am recalling -or perhaps,



I ought to say, of the bearing of these facts on the



use of statistical physics in the living cell will



follow later. But let me draw attention at this



point to the fact that 300 A is only about 100 or



150 atomic distances in a liquid or in a solid, so



that a gene contains certainly not more than



about a million or a few million atoms. That



number is much too small (from the /v point of



view) to entail an orderly and lawful behaviour



according to statistical physics -and that means



according to physics. It is too small, even if all



these atoms played the same role, as they do in a



gas or in a drop of liquid. And the gene is most



certainly not just a homogeneous drop of liquid.



It is probably a large protein molecule, in which



every atom, every radical, every heterocyclic



ring plays an individual role, more or less



different from that played by any of the other



similar atoms, radicals, or rings. This, at any rate,



is the opinion of leading geneticists such as



Haldane and Darlington, and we shall soon have



to refer to genetic experiments which come very



near to proving it.






PERMANENCE



Let us now turn to the second highly relevant



question: What degree of permanence do we



encounter in hereditary properties and what must



we therefore attribute to the material structures



which carry them? The answer to this can really



be given without any special investigation. The



mere fact that we speak of hereditary properties



indicates that we recognize the permanence to be



of the almost absolute. For we must not forget




haemophilia, dichromasy, etc. Such features we



may conveniently select for studying the laws of



heredity. But actually it is the whole (four-


dimensional) pattern of the 'phenotype', the all



the visible and manifest nature of the individual,



which is reproduced without appreciable change



for generations, permanent within centuries -


though not within tens of thousands of years -and


borne at each transmission by the material in a



structure of the nuclei of the two cells which



unite to form the fertilized egg cell. That is a



marvel -than which only one is greater; one that,



if intimately connected with it, yet lies on a



different plane. I mean the fact that we, whose



total being is entirely based on a marvellous



interplay of this very kind, yet if all possess the



power of acquiring considerable knowledge



about it. I think it possible that this knowledge



may advance to little just a short of a complete



understanding -of the first marvel. The second



may well be beyond human understanding.






CHAPTER 3



Mutations






'JUMP-LIKE'



MUTATIONS -THE



WORKING- GROUND OF NATURAL



SELECTION



The general facts which we have just put forward


in evidence of the durability claimed for the gene


structure, are perhaps too familiar to us to be



striking or to be regarded as convincing. Here,



for once, the common saying that exceptions



prove the rule is actually true. If there were no



exceptions to the likeness between children and



parents, we should have been deprived not only



of all those beautiful experiments which have



revealed to us the detailed mechanism of



heredity,



but also of that grand, million-fold



experiment of Nature, which forges the species






14


by natural selection and survival of the fittest.



Let me take this last important subject as the



starting-point for presenting the relevant facts -


again with an apology and a reminder that I am



not a biologist. We know definitely, today, that



Darwin was mistaken in regarding the small,



continuous, accidental variations, that are bound



to occur even in the most homogeneous



population, as the material on which natural



selection works. For it has been proved that they



are not inherited. The fact is important enough to



be illustrated briefly. If you take a crop of




pure-strain barley, and measure, ear by ear, the



length of its awns and plot the result of your



statistics, you will get a bell-shaped curve as



shown in Fig. 7, where the number of ears with a



definite length of awn is plotted against the



length. In other words: a definite medium length



prevails, and deviations in either direction occur



with certain frequencies. Now pick out a group



of ears (as indicated by blackening) with awns



noticeably beyond the average, but sufficient in



number to be sown in a field by themselves and



give a new crop. In making the same statistics



for this, Darwin would have expected to find the



corresponding curve shifted to the right. In other



words, he would have expected to produce by



selection an increase of the average length of the



awns. That is not the case, if a truly pure-bred strain of


barley has been used. The new



statistical curve, obtained from the selected crop,



is identical with the first one, and the same



would be the case if ears with particularly short



awns had been selected for seed. Selection has



no effect -because the small, continuous



variations are not inherited. They are obviously



not based on the structure of the hereditary



substance, they are accidental. But about forty



years ago the Dutchman de Vries discovered that



in the offspring even of thoroughly pure-bred



stocks, a very small number of individuals, say



two or three in tens of thousands, turn up with



small but 'jump- like' changes, the expression




jump-like' not meaning that the change is so



very considerable, but that there is a



discontinuity inasmuch as there are no



intermediate forms between the unchanged and



the few changed. De Vries called that a mutation.



The significant fact is the discontinuity. It



reminds a physicist of quantum theory -no



intermediate energies occurring between two



neighbouring energy levels. He would be



inclined to call de Vries's mutation theory,



figuratively, the quantum theory of biology. We



shall see later that this is much more



than figurative. The mutations are actually due to



quantum jumps in the gene molecule. But



quantum theory was but two years old when de



Vries first published his discovery, in 1902.



Small wonder that it took another generation to



discover the intimate connection!





THEY BREED TRUE, THAT IS, THEY ARE



PERFECTL


Y INHERITIED



Mutations are inherited as perfectly as the



original, correctly unchanged characters were.



To give an example, in the first crop of barley



considered above a few ears might turn up



with awns considerably outside the range of



variability shown in Fig. 7, say with no awns at



all. They might represent a de Vries mutation



and would then breed perfectly true, that is to



We must say, all their descendants would be



equally awnless. Hence a mutation is definitely a



change in the hereditary without treasure and has



to be accounted for by some change in the



hereditary substance. Actually most of the



important breeding experiments, which have



revealed to us the mechanism of by a heredity,



consisted in a careful analysis of the



offspring obtained by crossing, according to a



preconceived plan, mutated (or, in many cases,



multiply mutated) with non-mutated or with



differently mutated individuals. On the other



hand, by virtue of their breeding true, mutations



are a suitable material on which natural selection




15


may work and produce the species as described



by Darwin, by eliminating the unfit and letting



the fittest survive. In Darwin's theory, you



just have to substitute 'mutations' for his 'slight



accidental variations' (just as quantum theory



substitutes 'quantum jump' for 'continuous



transfer of energy'). In all other respects little



change was necessary in Darwin's theory, that is,



if I am correctly interpreting the view held by the



majority of biol ogists.






LOCALIZATION, RECESSIVITY AND



DOMINANCE



We must now review some other fundamental



facts and notions about mutations, again in a



slightly dogmatic manner, without showing



directly how they spring, one by one, from the



experimental evidence. We should expect a



definite observed mutation to be caused by a



change in a definite region in one of the



chromosomes. And so it is. It is important to



state that we know definitely, that it is a change



in one chromosome only, but not in the



corresponding 'locus' of the homologous



chromosome. Fig. 8 indicates this schematically,



the cross denoting the mutated a locus. The fact



that only one chromosome is affected is revealed



when the mutated individual (often called



'mutant') is crossed with a non-mutated one. For



exactly half of the offspring exhibit the mutant



character and half the normal one. That is what is



to be expected as a consequence of the



separation of the two chromosomes on meiosis



in the mutant as shown, very schematically, in



Fig. 9. This is a 'pedigree', representing every



individual (of three consecutive generations)



simply by the pair of chromosomes in question.



Please realize that if the mutant had both its



chromosomes affected, all the children would



receive the same (mixed) inheritance, different



from that of either parent. But experimenting in



this domain is not as simple as would appear



from what has just been said. It is complicated




by the second important fact, viz. that mutations



are very often latent. What does that mean? In



the mutant the two copies of the code-script are



no longer identical; they present two different



'readings' or 'versions', at any rate in that one



place. Perhaps it is well to point out at once that,



while it might be tempting, it would nevertheless



be entirely wrong to regard the original version



as 'orthodox', and the mutant version as 'heretic'.



We have to is regard them, in principle, as being



of equal right -for the normal characters have



also


arisen


from


mutations.


What


actually


happens


is


that the 'pattern' of the individual, as a



general rule, follows either the one or the other



rte version, which may be the normal or the



mutant one. The -version which is followed is



called dominant, the other, recessive; in other



words, the mutation is called dominant or




recessive, according to whether it is immediately



effective in changing the pattern or not.



Recessive mutations are even more frequent than



dominant ones and are very important, though at



first they do not show up at all. To affect the



pattern, they have to be present in both



chromosomes (see Fig. 10). Such individuals can



be produced when two equal recessive mutants



happen to be crossed with each other or when a



mutant is crossed with itself; this is possible in



hermaphroditic plants and even happens



spontaneously. An easy reflection shows that in



these cases about one-quarter of the offspring



will be of this type and thus visibly exhibit the



mutated pattern.






INTRODUCING SOME TECHNICAL



LANGUAGE



I think it will make for clarity to explain here a



few technical terms. For what I called 'version of



the code-script' -be it the original one or a mutant



one -the term 'allele' has been; adopted. When



the versions are different, as indicated in Fig. 8,



the individual is called heterozygous, with



respect to that locus. When they are equal, as in



16


the non-mutated individual or in the case of Fig.



10, they are called homozygous. Thus a recessive



allele influences the pattern only when



homozygous, whereas a dominant allele



produces the same pattern, whether homozygous



or only heterozygous. Colour is very often



dominant over lack of colour (or white). Thus,



for example, a pea will flower white only when it



has the 'recessive allele responsible for white' in



both chromosomes in question, when it is



'homozygous for white'; it will then breed true,



and all its descendants will be white. But one 'red



allele' (the other being white; 'heterozygous') will



make it flower red, and so will two red alleles



('homozygous'). The difference of the latter two



cases will only show up in the offspring,



when the heterozygous red will produce some



white descendants, and the homozygous red will



breed true. The fact that two individuals may be



exactly alike in their outward appearance, yet



differ in their inheritance, is so important that an



exact differentiation is desirable. The geneticist



says they have the same phenotype, but different



genotype. The contents of the preceding



paragraphs could thus be summarized in the brief,


but highly technical statement: A recessive allele



influences the phenotype only when the



genotype is homozygous. We shall use these



technical expressions occasionally, but shall



recall their meaning to the reader where



necessary.






THE HARMFUL EFFECT OF




CLOSE-BREEDING




Recessive mutations, as long as they are only



heterozygous, are of course no working- ground



for natural selection. If they are detrimental, as



mutations very often are, they will nevertheless



not be eliminated, because they are latent. Hence



quite a host of unfavourable mutations may



accumulate and do no immediate damage. But



they are, of course, transmitted to that half of the



offspring, and that has an important application




to man, cattle, poultry or any other species, the



good physical qualities of which are of



immediate concern to us. In Fig. 9 it is assumed



that a male individual (say, for concreteness,



myself) carries such a recessive detrimental



mutation heterozygously, so that it does not



show up. Assume that my wife is free of it. Then



half of our children (second line) will also carry



it -again heterozygously. If all of them are again



mated with non-mutated partners (omitted from



the diagram, to avoid reed confusion), a quarter



of our grandchildren, on the average, will be



affected in the same way. No danger of the evil



ever becoming manifest arises, unless of equally



affected individuals are crossed with each other,



when, as an easy reflection shows, one-quarter of



their children, being homozygous, would



manifest the damage. Next to self-fertilization



(only possible in hermaphrodite plants) the



greatest danger would be a marriage between a



son and a daughter of mine. Each of them



standing an even chance of being latently



affected or not, one-quarter of these incestuous



unions would be dangerous inasmuch as




one-quarter of its children would manifest the



damage. The danger factor for an incestuously



bred child is thus 1: 16. In the same way the



danger: factor works out to be 1 :64 for the



offspring of a union between two ('clean-bred')



grand- children of mine who are first cousins.



These do not seem to be but overwhelming odds,



and actually the second case is usually tolerated.



But do not forget that we have analysed the



consequences of only one possible latent injury



in one partner of the ancestral couple ('me and



my wife'). Actually both of them are quite likely



to harbour more than one latent deficiency of this



kind. If you know that you yourself harbour a definite


one, you have to reckon with l out of 8



of your first cousins sharing it! Experiments with



plants and animals seem to indicate that in



addition to comparatively rare deficiencies of a



serious kind, there seem to be a host of minor




17


ones whose chances combine to deteriorate the



offspring of close-breeding as a whole. Since we



are no longer inclined to eliminate failures in the



harsh way the Lacedemonians used to adopt in



the Taygetos mountain, we have to take a



particularly serious view about these things in



the case of man, were natural selection of the



fittest is largely retrenched, nay, turned to the



contrary. The anti-selective effect of the modern



mass slaughter of the healthy youth of all nations



is hardly outweighed by the consideration that in



more primitive conditions war may have had a



positive value in letting the fittest survive.






GENERAL AND HISTORICAL REMARKS




The fact that the recessive allele, when



heterozygous, is completely overpowered by the



dominant and produces no visible effects at all,



is amazing. It ought at least to mentioned that



there are exceptions to this behaviour. When



a homozygous white snapdragon is crossed with,



equally homozygous, crimson snapdragon, all



the immediate descendants are intermediate in



colour, i.e. they are pink (not crimson, as might



be expected). A much more important case of



two alleles exhibiting their influence



simultaneously occurs in blood-groups -but we



cannot enter into that here. I should not be



astonished if at long last recessivity should turn



our to be capable of degrees and to depend on



the sensitivity of the tests we apply to examine



the ‘phenotype’. This is perhaps the place for a



word on the early history of genetics. The



backbone of the theory, the law of inheritance, to



successive generations, of properties in which



the parents differ, and more especially the



important distinction recessive- dominant, are due


to the now world famous Augustininan Abbot



Gregor Mendel (1822-84). Mendel knew nothing



about mutations and chromosomes. In his



cloister gardens in Brunn (Brno) he made



experiments on the garden pea, of first which he



reared different varieties, crossing them and




watching their offspring in the 1st, 2nd, 3rd, ...,



generation. You might say, he experimented with



mutants which he found ready-made in nature.



The results he published as early as 1866 in the



Proceedings of the Naturforschender Verein in



Brunn. Nobody seems to have been particularly



interested in the abbot's hobby, and nobody,



certainly, had the faintest idea that his discovery



would in the twentieth century become the



lodestar of an entirely new branch of science,



easily the most interesting of our days. His paper



was forgotten and was only rediscovered in 1900,


simultaneously and independently, by Correns



(Berlin), de Vries (Amsterdam) and Tschermak



may (Vienna).






THE NECESSITY OF MUTATION BEING A



RARE EVENT



So far we have tended to fix our attention on



harmful mutations, which may be the more



numerous; but it must be definitely stated that we



do encounter advantageous mutations as well. If



a spontaneous mutation is a small step in the



development of the species, we get the



impression that some change is 'tried out' in



rather a haphazard fashion at the risk n, as of its



being injurious, in which case it is automatically



eliminated. This brings out one very important



point. In order to be suitable material for the



work of natural selection, mutations must be rare



events, as they actually are. If they were so



frequent that there was a considerable chance of,



say, a dozen of different mutations occurring in



the same individual, the injurious ones would, as



a rule, predominate over the advantageous ones



and the species, instead of being improved by



selection, would remain unimproved, or would



perish. The comparative conservatism which



results from the high degree of permanence of



the genes is essential. An analogy might be



sought in the working of a large manufacturing



plant in a factory. For developing better methods,



innovations, even if as yet unproved, must be





18


tried out. But in order to ascertain whether the



innovations improve or decrease the output, it



is essential that they should be introduced one at



a time, while all the other parts of the mechanism



are kept constant.






MUTA


TIONS INDUCED BY X-RAYS



We now have to review a most ingenious series



of genetical research work, which will prove to



be the most relevant feature of our analysis. The



percentage of mutations in the offspring, the




so-called mutation rate, can be increased to a



high multiple of the Small



natural mutation rate



by irradiating the parents with X-


rays or γ


-rays.



The mutations produced in this way differ in no



way (except by being more numerous) from



those occurring spontaneously, and one has the



impression that every ‘natural’ mutation can also



be induced by X-rays. In Drosophila many



special mutations recur spontaneously again and



to


you


again


in


the


vast


cultures;


they


have


been


located in the chromosome, as described on pp.



26-9, and have been given special names. There



have been found even what are called say, on



'multiple alleles', that is to say, two or more



different 'versions' and 'readings' -in addition to



the normal, non-mutated one -of the same place



in the chromosome code; that means not only



two, but three or more alternatives in that



particular one 'locus', any two of which are to



each other in the relation 'dominant- recessive'



when they occur simultaneously in their



corresponding loci of the two homologous



chromosomes. The experiments on X-ray-


produced mutations give the impression that



every particular 'transition', say from the normal



individual to a particular mutant, or conversely,



has its individual 'X-ray coefficient', indicating



the percentage of the offspring which turns out to



have mutated in that particular way, when a unit



dosage of X-ray has been applied to the parents,



before the offspring was engendered.






FIRST LAW.



MUTATION IS A SINGLE



EVENT




Furthermore, the laws governing the induced



mutation rate are extremely simple and



extremely illuminating. I follow here the report



of N. W. Timofeeff, in Biological Reviews, vol.



IX, 1934. To a considerable extent it refers to



that author's own beautiful work. The first law is



(I) The increase is exactly proportional to the



dosage of rays, so that one can actually speak (as



I did) of a coefficient of increase. We are so used



to simple proportionality that we are liable to



underrate the far-reaching consequences of this



simple law. To grasp them, we may remember



that the price of a commodity, for example, is not



always proportional to its amount. In ordinary



times a shopkeeper may be so much every



impressed by your having bought six oranges



from him, that, on your deciding to take after all



a whole dozen, he may give it to you for less



than double the price of the six. In times of



scarcity the opposite may happen. In the present



case, we conclude that the first half- dosage of



radiation, while causing, say, one out of a



thousand descendants to mutate, has not



influenced the rest at all, either in the way of



predisposing them for, or of immunizing them



against, mutation. For otherwise the second




half-dosage would not cause again just one out



of a thousand to mutate. Mutation is thus not an



accumulated effect, brought about by



consecutive small portions of radiation



reinforcing each other. It must consist in some



single event occurring in one chromosome



during irradiation. What kind of event?







SECOND LAW. LOCALIZATION OF THE



EVENT



This is answered by the second law, viz. (2) If



you vary the quality of the rays (wave-length)



within wide limits, from soft X-rays to fairly



hard γ


-rays, the coefficient remains constant,



provided you give the same dosage in so-called




19


r-units, that is to say, provided you measure the



dosage by the total amount standard substance



during the time and at the place where the



parents are exposed to the rays. As standard



substance one chooses air not only for



convenience, but also for the reason that organic



tissues are composed of elements of the same



atomic weight as air. A lower limit for the



amount of ionizations or allied processes



(excitations) in the tissue is obtained simply by



multiplying the number of ionizations in air by



the ratio of the densities. It is thus fairly obvious,


and is confirmed by a more critical investigation,


that the single event, causing a mutation, is just



an ionization (or similar process) occurring



within some 'critical' volume of the germ cell.



What is the size of this critical volume? It can be



estimated from the observed mutation rate by a



consideration of this kind: if a dosage of 50,000



ions per cm3 produces a chance of only 1:1000



for any particular gamete (that finds itself in the



irradiated district) to mutate in that particular



way, we conclude that the critical volume, the



'target' which has to be 'hit' by an ionization



for that mutation to occur, is only 1/1000 of



1/50000 of a cm3, that is to say, one fifty-


millionth of a cm3. The numbers are not the right


ones, but are used only by way of illustration. In



the actual estimate we follow M. Delbruck, in a



paper by Delbruck, N.W. Timofeeffand K.G


.



Zimmer, which will also be the principal source



of the theory to be expounded in the following



two chapters. He arrives there at a size of only



about ten average atomic distances cubed,



containing thus only about 103



= a thousand



atoms. The simplest interpretation of this result



is that there is a fair chance of producing that



mutation when an ionization (or excitation)



occurs not more than about '10 atoms away' from


some particular spot in the chromosome. We



shall discuss this in more detail presently. The



Timofeeff report contains a practical hint which I



cannot refrain from mentioning here, though it



has, of course, no bearing on our present



investigation. There are plenty of occasions in



modern life when a human being has to be exposed to


X-rays. The direct dangers involved,



as burns, X-ray cancer, sterilization, are well



known, and protection by lead screens, lead-


loaded aprons, etc., is provided, especially for



nurses and doctors who have to handle the rays



regularly. The point is, that even when these



imminent dangers to the individual are



successfully warded off, there appears to be the



indirect danger of small detrimental mutations



being produced in the germ cells -mutations of



the kind envisaged when we spoke of the



unfavourable results of close-breeding. To put it



drastically, though perhaps a little naively, the



injuriousness marriage between first cousins



might very this well be increased by the fact that



their grandmother had served for a long period as



an X-ray nurse. It is not a point that need worry



any individual personally. But any possibility of



gradually infecting the human race with



unwanted latent mutations ought to be a matter



of concern to the community.






CHAPTER 4




The Quantum-Mechanical Evidence




Thus, aided by the marvellously subtle



instrument of X-rays (which, as the physicist



remembers, revealed thirty years ago really the



detailed atomic lattice structures of crystals), the



united efforts of biologists and physicists have of



late succeeded in reducing the upper limit for the



size of the microscopic structure, being



responsible for a definite large-scale feature of



the individual- the 'size of a gene' -and reducing



it far below the estimates obtained on pp. 29-30.



We are now seriously faced with the question:



How can we, from the point of view of statistical



physics, reconcile the facts that the gene



structure seems to involve only a comparatively



small number of atoms (of the order of 1,000 and



20







possibly much less), and that value nevertheless



it displays a most regular and lawful activity



-


with a durability or permanence that borders



upon the miraculous? Let me throw the truly



amazing situation into relief once again. Several



members of the Habsburg dynasty have a



peculiar disfigurement of the lower lip



('Habsburger Lippe'). Its inheritance has been



studied carefully and published, complete with



historical portraits, by the Imperial Academy In



Vienna, under the auspices of the family. The



feature proves to be a genuinely Mendelian



'allele' to the normal form of the lip. Fixing our



attention on the portraits of a member of the



family in the sixteenth century and of his



descendant, living in the nineteenth, we may



safely assume that the material gene structure,



responsible for the abnormal feature, has been



carried on from generation to generation through


the centuries, faithfully reproduced at every one



of the not very numerous cell divisions that lie



between. Moreover, the number of atoms



involved in the responsible gene structure is



likely to be of the same order of magnitude as in



the cases tested by X-rays. The gene has been



kept at a temperature around 98°


F during all that



time. How are we to understand that it has



remained unperturbed by the disordering



tendency of the heat motion for centuries? A



physicist at the end of the last century would



have been at a loss to answer this question, if he



was prepared to draw only on those laws of



Nature which he could explain and which he



really understood. Perhaps, indeed, after a short



reflection on the statistical situation he would



have answered (correctly, as we shall see): These


material structures can only be molecules. Of the


existence, and sometimes very high stability, of



these associations of atoms, chemistry had



already acquired a widespread knowledge at the



time. But the knowledge was purely empirical.



The nature of a molecule was not understood -


the strong mutual bond of the atoms which keeps



a molecule in shape was a complete conundrum



to everybody. Actually, the answer proves to be



correct. But it is of limited value as long as the



enigmatic biological stability is traced back only



to an equally enigmatic chemical stability. The



evidence that two features, similar in appearance,



are based on the same principle, is always



precarious as long as the principle itself is



unknown.






EXPLICABLE BY QUANTUM THEORY




In this case it is supplied by quantum theory. In



the light of present knowledge, the mechanism of



heredity is closely related to, nay, founded on,



the very basis of quantum theory. This theory



was discovered by Max Planck in 1900. Modern



genetics can be dated from the rediscovery of



Mendel's paper by de Vries, Correns and



Tschermak (1900) and from de Vries's paper on



mutations (l901-3). Thus the births of the two



great theories nearly coincide, and it is small



wonder that both of them had to reach a certain



maturity before the connection could emerge. On



the side of quantum theory it took more than a



quarter of a century till in 1926-7 the quantum



theory of the chemical bond was outlined in its



general principles by W. Heitler and F. London.



The Heitler-London theory involves the most



subtle and intricate conceptions of the latest



development


of


quantum


theory


(called


'quantum


mechanics' or 'wave mechanics'). A presentation



without the use of calculus is well-nigh



impossible or would at least require another little



volume each like this. But fortunately, now that



all work has been done and has served to clarify



our thinking, it seems to be possible to point out



in a more direct manner the connection between



'quantum jumps' and mutations, to pick out at the



moment the most conspicuous item. That is what



we attempt here.






QUANTUM THEORY -DISCRETE STATES





QUANTUM JUMPS




21





-


-


-


-


-


-


-


-



本文更新与2021-02-28 19:52,由作者提供,不代表本网站立场,转载请注明出处:https://www.bjmy2z.cn/gaokao/683393.html

What_is_life_(生命是什么)_by_薛定谔的相关文章