关键词不能为空

当前您在: 主页 > 英语 >

语义学 蕴含与预设

作者:高考题库网
来源:https://www.bjmy2z.cn/gaokao
2021-02-27 15:24
tags:

-

2021年2月27日发(作者:礁石)


句子语义学



词和词之间有各种各样的意义关系,我们称之为


sense r elation



句子也一样,


可以有 各种意义关系。


句子语义学是在句子层面对意义


进行研究,并把 句子当成一个整体来看待。






Presupposition< /p>


前提


/


预设,这一概念是由哲学家弗雷格 (



)首先提


出来的。在言语交际中,我 们所说的一句句话并不是孤立的,相互之间毫无


联系的。相反前一句话和后一句话往往有 密切的联系。



Please open the door.



这句话的意思很清楚,< /p>


就是


“请把们打开”


< br>但是说这句话必须有一个前


提,那就是“现在要开的门再说话时是关着的”




所以从语义的角度来看,


句子所包含的


“前提”


和这个句子本身的意义有十


份密切的关系



句子的前提有这样的特点: 否定了句子本身,句子的前提保留不变。



John is married.















John exists.















John is not married.




Semantic presupposition and pragmatic presupposition


语义预设是对语句之间关系所做的逻辑分析,他面对的是一种不变的关


系:即 如果


P


在语义上预设


Q,

< p>


P


总是在语义上预设


Q




但在实际的语言活动中

< p>
(语用预设)



预设通常不是语义中稳定的不受约


束的部分。这也正是有些语言学家认为预设属于语用学而不属于语义学的主


要原因。一个重要的事实是,在一定的语境里,预设会消失,也就是说预设


具 有可消失性


(defeasibility)


。例如:



Sue cried before she finished her thesis.


Sue died before she finished her thesis.






What is Semantic Presupposition?





In


many


discussions


of


the


concept,


presupposition


is


treated


as


a


relationship


between two propositions by the linguists. If we say the sentence in (1a.) contains the


proposition


p


and the sentence in (1b.) contains the proposition


q,


then, using


>>


to


mean


?


presupposes


?


, we can represent the relationship as in (1c.).


(1)



a. Mary


?


s dog is cute.



(



p


)


b. Mary has a dog.





(=


q


)


c. p


>>



q


Interestingly, when we produce the opposite of the sentence in (1a.) by negating


it


(=


NOT


p),


as


in


(2a.),


we


find


that


the


relationship


of


presupposition


does


not


change. That is, the same proposition q, repeated as (2b.), continues to be presupposed


by NOT p, as shown in (2c.).


(2)




a. Mary


?


s dog isn


?


t cute.



(




NOT


p


)


b. Mary has a dog.



(=


q


)


c. NOT


p


>>



q


Presupposition is an inference


(推论)


to the proposition of the sentence. Take the


following sentences for example again:


e.g.



(3) John is married.







(4) John exists.







(5) John is not married.


Comment: if (3) is true, (4) is true; if (3) is not true, (4) is still true. In this case,


we can say both (3) and (5) presuppose (4). A presupposition is something the speaker


assumes


to


be


the


case


prior


to


making


an


utterance.


Speakers,


not


sentences,


have


presuppositions.


An


entailment



is


something


that


logically


follows


from


what


is


asserted in the utterance. Sentences, not speakers, have entailments.







Semantic presupposition


would be based on the following definition:


Sentence A semantically presupposes another sentence B iff


:


if and only if, iff


是充分必要条件



(a) in all situations where A is true, B is true


(b) in all situations where A is false, B is true





Types of presupposition




Potential presupposition: in the analysis of how speakers? assumptions are typically


expressed, presupposition has been associated with the use of a large number of words,


phrases,


and


structures.


These


linguistic


forms


shall


be


considered


as


indicators


of


potential presuppositions, which can only become actual presuppositions in contexts


with


speakers.


The


following


kinds


of


presuppositions


are


all


potential


presuppositions.


Now


we


?


ll


look


at


the


major


presupposition


types


marked


by


different linguistic features.



Existential presupposition: presuppose the existence of something.(my). It is not


only


assumed


to


be


present


in


possessive


constructions,


but


more


generally


in


any


definite descriptions such as definite noun phrase with determines


?


the


?


,


?


this


?


,


?


that


?

,


?


these


?


,


?


those


?


, etc. By using any of the expressions in (16), the speaker is assumed to


be committed to the existence of the entities named.


(16) e.g. The king of Sweden, the cat, the girl next door (Yule, 2004: 27)



Factive


presupposition:


presuppose


something


as


a


fact.(know).


A


number


of


factive


verbs,


such


as


?


realize


?



in


(17a)



and


?


regret


?



in


(17b),


as


well


as


phrases


involving


?


be


?


with


?


aware


?

< p>
in (17c),


?


odd


?


in (17d), and


?


glad


?


in (17e) have factive


presuppositions.


(17) a. She didn


?


t realize he was ill.








(


>>


He was ill)


b. We regret telling him.









(


>>


We told him)


c. I wasn


?


t aware that she was married.





(


>>


She was married)


d. It


isn?t


odd that he left early.





(


>>


He left early)


e. I


?


m glad that it


?


s over.






(


>>


It


?


s over)



The presupposed information following the verb


?know? can be treated as a fac


t,


and is described as a factive presupposition. Words like know, realize, regret as well


as phrases involving ?be? with ?aware?, ?odd?, and ?glad? have factive presuppositions.


(Yule, 2004: 27-28)




Lexical


presupposition:


when


a


specific


word


triggers


a


presupposition.


It


is


featured


by


implicative


verbs


like


?


manage

< p>
?


,


?


start


?


,


?


stop


?


,


?


fo rget


?


,


etc.


Generally


speaking, in lexical presupposition, the use of one form with its asserted meaning is


conventionally


interpreted


with


the


presupposition


that


another


(non-asserted)


meaning is understood.


Each


time


you


say


that


someone


?


managed< /p>


?



to


do


something,


the


asserted


meaning


is


that


the


person


succeeded


in


some


way.


When


you


say


that


someone


?


didn


?


t manage


?


, the asserted meaning is that the person did not succeed. In both cases,


however,


there


is


a


presupposition


(non- asserted)


that


the


person


?


tried


?



to


do


that


something. So,

< br>?


managed


?


is conventionally interpreted as asserting


?


succeeded


?


and


presupposing


?


tri ed


?


.




(18) a. He stopped smoking.



(


>>


He used to smoke)


b. They started complaining.



(


>>


They weren


?


t complaining before)


c. You


?


re late again.




(


>>


You were late before)


Lexical presupposition: in lexical presupposition, the use of one form with its


asserted


meaning


is


conventionally


interpreted


with


the


presupposition


that


another(non-asserted) meaning is understood. For example, someone


?managed? to do


something,


the


asserted


meaning


is


that


the


person


succeeded


in


some


way.



Someone ?didn?t manage?;


the asserted meaning is that the person did not succeed. In


both cases, there is a presupposition (non-


asserted) that the person ?tried? to do that


something.


So


?managed?



is


conventionally


interpreted


as


asserting


?succeeded?


and


presupposing ?tried?. Other examples, involving the lexical items, are ?stop?, ?start?,


and ?again?. (Yule, 2004: 28)




Structural presupposition: certain sentence structures presuppose something to be


true.(wh- questions).


We


might


say


that


speakers


can


use


such


structures


to


treat


information as presupposed (i.e. assumed to be true) and hence to be accepted as true


by the listener.


For example, the wh-question construction in English, as shown in (19a) and (19b),


is


conventionally


interpreted


with


the


presupposition


that


the


information


after


the


wh-form is already known to be the case.



a. When did he leave?




(


>>


He left)


b. Where did you buy the bike?




(


>>


You bought the bike)





Certain sentence structures have been analyzed as conventionally and regularly


presupposing that part of the structure is


already assumed to


be true. We might


say


that speakers can use such structures to treat information as presupposed (i.e. assumed


to be true) and hence to be accepted as true by listener. For example, the wh-question


construction in English is conventionally interpreted as that the information after the


wh-form


is


already


known


to


be


the


case.


Such


structurally-based


presuppositions


may represent subtle ways of making information that the speaker believes appear to


be what the listener should believe.(wh-questions)




Non-factive presupposition: It is one that is assumed not to be true. Verbs like


?


dream


?


,


?


imag ine


?


, and


?


pretend


?


, as shown in (20), are used with the presupposition


that what follows is not true.


(20). a. I dreamed that I was rich.



(


>>


I was not rich)


b. We imagined we were in New York.



(


>>


we were not in New York)


He pretends to be ill.





(


>>


He is not ill)




Counter- factural presupposition: What is presupposed is not only not true, but is


the opposite of what is true, or


?


contrary to facts


?


.



(Conditional structure)



A


conditional


structure


of


the


type


shown


in


(21),


generally


called


a


counterfactual conditional, presupposes that the information in the if-clause is not true


at the time of utterance.


(21). If you were my friend, you would have helped me.


(


>>


you are not my friend)





Summary:


Type


existential




factive


non-factive


lexical


structural






counterfactural





The properties of presuppositions





Cancel ability / Defeasibility


:




Levinson(1983:186)


states


that


they


can


be


cancelled


out


by


either


the


immediate linguistic context


or by some


wider


context


or mode of discourse.


If we


say


?


The committee failed to reach a decision


?


, it presupposes that they tried, but we


can cancel out that presupposition if we add


?


because they didn


?


t even get round to


discussing it


?


. Similarly, we can argue presupposition out of the way by a variant on


the


reductio


ad


absurdum


(the


disproof


of


a


proposition


by


showing


that


its


conclusion can only be absurd) mode of discourse:


?


He didn


?


t do it, and she didn


?


t do


it



In fact, nobody did it


?.



They are defensible in (a) certain discourse contexts, (b)


certain intra- sentential context. This property will prove to be the undoing(doing away


with) of any possible semantic theory of presupposition. They are defeasible in certain


intra- sentential contexts and certain discourse context, for example,


(1) Sue cried


before


she finished her thesis.


(2) Sue finished her thesis.


(3)Sue died


before


she finished her thesis.


In


Sentence(3)


the


presupposition


seems


to


drop


out,


since


we


generally


hold


that


people do not do things after they die, it follows that she could not have finished her


thesis.


They


are


liable


to


evaporate


in


certain


contexts,


either


immediate


linguistic


context or the less immediate discourse context, or on circumstances where contrary


assumptions are made.(Levinson,2001, p187)


Another kind of contextual defeasibility arises in certain kinds of discourse contexts.


For example, the cleft sentence 1 is supposed to presuppose 2:


1. It isn?t Luke who will betray you.



2. Someone will betray you.


You say that someon


e in this room will betray you. Well maybe so. But it won?t be


Luke


who


will


betray


you,


it


won?t


be


Paul,


it


won?t


be


Matthew,


and


it


certainly


won?t be John. Therefore no one in this room is actually going to betray you



Example


the X


I regret leaving




He pretended to go


He managed to escape


When did she die?


If I weren


?


t ill,


Presupposition


>>



X exists


>>



I left


>>



He didn


?


t go


>>



He tried to escape


>>



She died


>>



I am ill


Here


each


of


the


cleft


sentence(It


won?t


be


Luke,


etc.)should


presuppose


that


there


will


be


someone


who


will


betray


the


addressee.


But


the


whole


purpose


of


the


utterance


1


is,


of


course,


to


persuade


the


addressee


that


no


one


will


betray


him,


as


stated in the conclusion. So the presupposition is again defeated; it was adopted as a


counterfactual


assumption


to


argue


to


the


untenability


(


站不住脚


)


of


such


an


assumption.


So far we have shown that some of the core examples of presuppositional phenomena are subject to presupposition


cancellation in certain kinds of context, namely:


(i)



Where it is common knowledge that the presupposition is false, the speaker is not assumed to be committed


to the truth of the presupposition


(ii) Where what is said, taken together with background assumptions, is inconsistent with what is presupposed,


the presuppositions are cancelled, and are not assumed to be held by the speaker


(iii) In certain kinds of discourse contexts, presuppositions can systematically fail to survive.


3.4.2 Presuppositions are apparently tied to particular aspects of surface structure


. This property may serve


to distinguish presupposition from conversational implicatures (which are tied to the context rather than the surface


structure.), the other major form of pragmatic inference.( Levinson, S. C. 2001)




There are no doubt many other kinds of contextual defeasibility as well, but these examples are sufficient to


establish that presuppositions are defeasible by virtue of contrary


beliefs held in a context. There are also many


kinds of intra-sentential cancellation of suspension of presuppositions.(Levinson, 190)



3.4.3 Projection in presupposition


There is a basic expectation that the presupposition of a simple sentence will


continue to be true when that simple sentence becomes part of a more complex sentence. This is one version of the


general idea that the meaning of the whole sentence is a combination of the meaning of its parts. However, the


meaning of some presuppositions (as


?


parts


?


) does not survive to become the meaning of some complex sentences


(as


?


wholes


?


).


This


is


known


as


the


projection


problem


.


(Yule,


2004:


P


30-33



)


Another


explanation


given


by


Levinson


(Levinson,


1983:


191)


is


that


Frege


held


that


meanings


of


sentences


are


compositional,


i.e.


that


the


meaning


of


the


whole


expression


is


a


function


of


the


meaning


of


the


parts.


It


was


originally


suggested


by


Langendoen & Savin (1971) that this was true of presuppositions too, and moreover that the set of presupposition


of


the


complex


whole


is


the


simple


sum


of


the


presuppositions


of


the


parts,


i.e.


if


S


0


is


a


complex


sentence


containing


sentences


S


1,


S


2



S

< p>
n


as


constituents,


then


the


presuppositions of




S


0


=


the


presuppositions


of


S


1


+


the


presuppositions of S


2



+ the presuppositions of S


n


.



But such a simple solution to the presuppositions of complex


sentences is far from correct, and it has proved in fact extremely difficult to formulate a theory that will predict


correctly which presuppositions of component clauses will in fact be inherited/maintained by the complex whole.


This compositional problem is known as the


projection problem


for presuppositions, and the particular behaviour


of


presuppositions


in


complex


sentences


turns


out


to


be


the


really


distinctive


characteristic


of


presuppositions.




(The


Chinese


version


may


be


a


little


easier


to


understand:


详见



索振羽


,


《语用学教程》

2000.


北京大学出版社


P


13 6-140


)





Presupposition triggers:


Some of the kinds of words and structures that seem to trigger presuppositions.


Definite


noun


phrase/definite


descriptions:



words


like



the,


this,


that,


these,


those



and


possessives


like


my,


Mary’


s,


your,


prepositional


phrase


like


with



(two


heads)


,


in


,


etc.


trigger



the


basic


kind


of


presupposition.


The


possessives lead to a particularly strong presupposition about the existence of something; this is sometimes called


existential presupposition.



(Peccei, p20)


John saw/didn


?


t see the man with two heads.



there exists a man with two heads


WH-words like


when, why, how, etc


.


used either to ask questions or to introduce a subordinate clause to trigger


the presupposition that the speaker has assumed “the person in question did something” is true. (Peccei, p 21


)


Mr. Givens,


why


is it important for people to understand body language---that is, communication by



means of


movements and gestures?


Where


do we get mannerisms such as these?


Verbs that can trigger presuppositions: implicative verbs, factive verbs, change of state verbs and verbs of


judging.


1) Implicative verbs



含蓄动词)


: manage, forget, happen, avoid etc. triggers the presupposition that some actions


were conducted(manage), not expected(happen), or should have been conducted(forget).


John


managed


/didn?t


manage


to open the door



John tried to open the door


John forg


ot /didn?t forget to lock the door




John ought to have locked, or intended to lock, the door


some


further


implicative


predicates:


X


happened


to


V



X


didn?t


plan


or


intend


to


V;


X


avoid


Ving



X


was


expected to, or usually did, or ought to V


2) factive verbs(


述实动词


/


事实动词


a verb followed by a clause which the speaker or writer considers to express


a fact


:




know, realize, regret, deplore


(谴责)


, I am aware, it is strange, it is odd that, be sorry that, be proud that,



be indifferent that,



be glad that, be sad that, etc. triggers the presupposition that what follows is a fact



(Peccei,


p22)


Martha regrets /doesn?t


regret



drinking John?s home brew



)


Martha drank John?s home brew



It was


odd


/it was not


odd


how proud he was.



he was proud


3) change of state verbs



状态变化动词)


: stop, continue, keep, arrive, begin, come, enter, transform, turn, finish,



carry on, cease, leave, enter, go, etc. trigger the presupposition that the action was (A) going on before, (B) not


going on before.


John stopped /didn?t stop beating his wife




John had been beating his wife


4) verbs of judging


(评价动词)


:


accuse, charge, criticize, repudiate/criticize,


rs the presupposition that


what follows is the judgement or comments made by the subject on the topic or people in question. This kind of


implication is, arguably, not really presuppositional at all; for, unlike other presuppositions, the implications are


not attributed to the speaker, so much as to the subject of the verb of judging.


Ian


criticized


/ didn?t


criticize


Agatha for running away



(Ian thinks)Agatha ran away




The police


charged


John with reckless driving.





John drove recklessly.










5) Verbs like pretend, imagine, dream


,etc. triggers the


resupposition that what follows is


fiction.


Iteratives: again, anymore, return, another time, to come back, restore, repeat,



for the



-nth time


Carter


returned


/didn?t r


eturn


to power

-


-


-


-


-


-


-


-



本文更新与2021-02-27 15:24,由作者提供,不代表本网站立场,转载请注明出处:https://www.bjmy2z.cn/gaokao/674539.html

语义学 蕴含与预设的相关文章

  • 余华爱情经典语录,余华爱情句子

    余华的经典语录——余华《第七天》40、我不怕死,一点都不怕,只怕再也不能看见你——余华《第七天》4可是我再也没遇到一个像福贵这样令我难忘的人了,对自己的经历如此清楚,

    语文
  • 心情低落的图片压抑,心情低落的图片发朋友圈

    心情压抑的图片(心太累没人理解的说说带图片)1、有时候很想找个人倾诉一下,却又不知从何说起,最终是什么也不说,只想快点睡过去,告诉自己,明天就好了。有时候,突然会觉得

    语文
  • 经典古训100句图片大全,古训名言警句

    古代经典励志名言100句译:好的药物味苦但对治病有利;忠言劝诫的话听起来不顺耳却对人的行为有利。3良言一句三冬暖,恶语伤人六月寒。喷泉的高度不会超过它的源头;一个人的事

    语文
  • 关于青春奋斗的名人名言鲁迅,关于青年奋斗的名言鲁迅

    鲁迅名言名句大全励志1、世上本没有路,走的人多了自然便成了路。下面是我整理的鲁迅先生的名言名句大全,希望对你有所帮助!当生存时,还是将遭践踏,将遭删刈,直至于死亡而

    语文
  • 三国群英单机版手游礼包码,三国群英手机单机版攻略

    三国群英传7五神兽洞有什么用那是多一个武将技能。青龙飞升召唤出东方的守护兽,神兽之一的青龙。玄武怒流召唤出北方的守护兽,神兽之一的玄武。白虎傲啸召唤出西方的守护兽,

    语文
  • 不收费的情感挽回专家电话,情感挽回免费咨询

    免费的情感挽回机构(揭秘情感挽回机构骗局)1、牛牛(化名)向上海市公安局金山分局报案,称自己为了挽回与女友的感情,被一家名为“实花教育咨询”的情感咨询机构诈骗4万余元。

    语文