关键词不能为空

当前您在: 主页 > 英语 >

A Review of B. F. Skinner's Verbal Behavior

作者:高考题库网
来源:https://www.bjmy2z.cn/gaokao
2021-02-01 13:12
tags:

-

2021年2月1日发(作者:小时)


A Review of B. F. Skinner's


Verbal Behavior



Noam Chomsky


In Leon A. Jakobovits and Murray S. Miron (eds.),


Readings in the Psychology of Language


, Prentice-Hall,


1967, pp. 142-143


Preface


Rereading this review after eight years, I find little of substance that I would change if I were to write it today. I am not


aware of any theoretical or experimental work that challenges its conclusions; nor, so far as I know, has there been any


attempt to meet the criticisms that are raised in the review or to show that they are erroneous or ill-founded.


I had intended this review not specifically as a criticism of Skinner's speculations regarding language, but rather as a


more


general


critique of


behaviorist


(I


would


now


prefer to


say


as


to


the


nature


of


higher


mental


processes.


My


reason


for


discussing


Skinner's


book


in


such


detail


was


that


it


was


the


most


careful


and


thoroughgoing presentation of such speculations, an evaluation that I feel is still accurate. Therefore, if the conclusions


I attempted to substantiate in the review are correct, as I believe they are, then Skinner's work can be regarded as, in


effect, a reductio ad absurdum of behaviorist assumptions. My personal view is that it is a definite merit, not a defect,


of


Skinner's


work


that


it


can


be


used


for


this


purpose,


and


it


was


for


this


reason


that


I


tried


to


deal


with


it


fairly


exhaustively. I do not see how his proposals can be improved upon, aside from occasional details and oversights, within


the framework of the general assumptions that he accepts. I do not, in other words, see any way in which his proposals


can


be


substantially


improved


within


the


general


framework


of


behaviorist


or


neobehaviorist,


or,


more


generally,


empiricist


ideas


that


has


dominated


much


of


modern


linguistics,


psychology,


and


philosophy.


The


conclusion


that


I


hoped to establish in the review, by discussing these speculations in their most explicit and detailed form, was that the


general point of view was largely mythology, and that its widespread acceptance is not the result of empirical support,


persuasive reasoning, or the absence of a plausible alternative.


If I were writing today on the same topic, I would try to make it more clear than I did that I was discussing Skinner's


proposals as a paradigm example of a futile tendency in modern speculation about language and mind. I would also be


somewhat less apologetic and hesitant about proposing the alternative view sketched in Sections 5 and 11 -- and also


less


ahistorical


in


proposing


this


alternative,


since


in


fact


it


embodies


assumptions


that


are


not


only


plausible


and


relatively


well-confirmed,


so


it


appears


to


me,


but


also


deeply


rooted


in


a


rich


and


largely


forgotten


tradition


of


rationalist psychology and linguistics. I have tried to correct this imbalance in later publications (Chomsky, 1962, 1964,


1966; see also Miller et al., 1960; Katz and Postal, 1964; Fodor, 1965; Lenneberg, 1966).


I think it would also have been valuable to try to sketch some of the reasons -- and there were many -- that have made


the


view


I


was


criticizing


seem


plausible


over


a


long


period,


and


also


to discuss the


reasons for the


decline


of


the


alternative rationalist conception which, I was suggesting, should be rehabilitated. Such a discussion would, perhaps,


have helped to place the specific critique of Skinner in a more meaningful context.


References in the Preface



Chomsky, N.,


Suppes, and A. Tarski. Stanford; Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1962.


----------, Current Issues in Linguistic Theory. The Hague: Mouton and Co., 1964.


----------, Cartesian Linguistics. New York: Harper and Row, Publishers, 1966.


Fodor, J.,


Katz, J. and P. Postal, An Integrated Theory of Linguistic Description. Cambridge, Mass: M.I.T. Press, 1964.


Lenneberg, E., Biological Bases of Language. (In press.)


Miller, G. A., E. Galanter, and K. H. Pribram, Plans


and the Structure of Behavior. New York: Holt, Rhinehart, and


Winston, Inc., 1960.


The Review



by Noam Chomsky




I


A great many


linguists


and philosophers concerned


with


language


have expressed the


hope


that


their studies


might


ultimately be embedded in a framework provided by behaviorist psychology, and that refractory areas of investigation,


particularly those in which meaning is involved, will in this way be opened up to fruitful exploration. Since this volume is


the first large-scale attempt to incorporate the major aspects of linguistic behavior within a behaviorist framework, it


merits and will undoubtedly receive careful attention. Skinner is noted for his contributions


to the study of animal


behavior. The book under review is the product of study of linguistic behavior extending over more than twenty years.


Earlier


versions


of


it


have


been


fairly


widely


circulated,


and


there


are


quite


a


few


references


in


the


psychological


literature to its major ideas.


The problem to which this book is addressed is that of giving a


analysis, Skinner means identification of the variables that control this behavior and specification of how they interact


to determine a particular verbal response. Furthermore, the controlling variables are to be described completely in


terms of such notions as stimulus, reinforcement, deprivation, which have been given a reasonably clear meaning in


animal experimentation. In other words, the goal of the book is to provide a way to predict and control verbal behavior


by observing and manipulating the physical environment of the speaker.


Skinner feels that recent advances in the laboratory study of animal behavior permit us to approach this problem with a


certain optimism, since


fairly well understood ... the results [of this experimental work] have been surprisingly free of species restrictions.


Recent work has shown that the methods can be extended to human behavior without serious modification


It


is


important


to


see


clearly


just


what


it


is


in


Skinner's


program


and


claims


that


makes


them


appear


so


bold


and


remarkable, It is not primarily the fact that he has set functional analysis as his problem, or that he limits himself to


study of observables, i.e., input- output relations. What is so surprising is the particular limitations he has imposed on


the way in which the observables of behavior are to be studied, and, above all, the particularly simple nature of the


function


which,


he


claims,


describes


the


causation


of


behavior.


One


would


naturally


expect


that


prediction


of


the


behavior


of


a complex


organism


(or machine)


would


require, in


addition


to


information


about


external stimulation,


knowledge of the internal structure of the organism, the ways in which it processes input information and organizes its


own


behavior.


These


characteristics


of


the


organism


are


in


general


a


complicated


product


of


inborn


structure,


the


genetically determined course of maturation, and past experience. Insofar as independent neurophysiological evidence


is not available, it is obvious that inferences concerning the structure of the organism are based on observation of


behavior and outside events. Nevertheless, one's estimate of the relative importance of external factors and internal


structure in the determination of behavior will have an important effect on the direction of research on linguistic (or


any other) behavior, and on the kinds of analogies from animal behavior studies that will be considered relevant or


suggestive.


Putting it differently, anyone who sets himself the problem of analyzing the causation of behavior will (in the absence of


independent neurophysiological evidence) concern himself with the only data available, namely the record of inputs to


the organism and the organism's present response, and will try to describe the function specifying the response in terms


of


the history of inputs. This


is nothing more than the definition of his problem. There are no possible grounds for


argument


here,


if


one


accepts


the


problem


as


legitimate,


though


Skinner


has


often


advanced


and


defended


this


definition of a problem as if it were a thesis which other investigators reject. The differences that arise between those


who


affirm


and


those


who


deny


the


importance


of


the


specific



of


the


organism


to


learning


and


performance


concern


the


particular


character


and


complexity


of


this


function,


and


the


kinds


of


observations


and


research necessary for arriving at a precise specification of it. If the contribution of the organism is complex, the only


hope of predicting behavior even in a gross way will be through a very indirect program of research that begins by


studying the detailed character of the behavior itself and the particular capacities of the organism involved.


Skinner's thesis is that external factors consisting of present stimulation and the history of reinforcement (in particular,


the frequency,


arrangement,


and


withholding


of reinforcing


stimuli)


are


of


overwhelming


importance, and


that


the


general


principles


revealed


in


laboratory


studies


of


these


phenomena


provide


the


basis


for


understanding


the


complexities


of


verbal


behavior.


He


confidently


and


repeatedly


voices


his


claim


to


have


demonstrated


that


the


contribution of the speaker is quite trivial and elementary, and that precise prediction of verbal behavior involves only


specification of the few external factors that he has isolated experimentally with lower organisms.


Careful study of this book (and of the research on which it draws) reveals, however, that these astonishing claims are far


from


justified.


It


indicates,


furthermore,


that


the


insights


that


have


been


achieved


in


the


laboratories


of


the


reinforcement theorist, though quite genuine, can be applied to complex human behavior only in the most gross and


superficial


way,


and


that


speculative


attempts


to


discuss


linguistic


behavior


in


these


terms


alone


omit


from


consideration


factors


of


fundamental


importance


that


are,


no


doubt,


amenable


to


scientific


study,


although


their


specific character cannot at present be precisely formulated. Since Skinner's work is the most extensive attempt to


accommodate human behavior involving higher mental faculties within a strict behaviorist schema of the type that has


attracted


many


linguists


and


philosophers,


as


well


as


psychologists,


a


detailed


documentation


is


of


independent


interest. The magnitude of the failure of this attempt to account for verbal behavior serves as a kind of measure of the


importance


of


the


factors


omitted


from


consideration,


and


an


indication


of


how


little


is


really


known


about


this


remarkably complex phenomenon.


The force of Skinner's argument lies in the enormous wealth and range of examples for which he proposes a functional


analysis. The only way to evaluate the success of his program and the correctness of his basic assumptions about verbal


behavior is to review these examples in detail and to determine the precise character of the concepts in terms of which


the functional analysis is presented. Section 2 of this review describes the experimental context with respect to which


these


concepts


are


originally


defined.


Sections


3


and


4


deal


with


the


basic


concepts


--


stimulus,


response,


and


reinforcement, Sections 6 to 10 with the new descriptive machinery developed specifically for the description of verbal


behavior. In Section 5 we consider the status of the fundamental claim, drawn from the laboratory, which serves as the


basis for the analogic guesses about human behavior that have been proposed by many psychologists. The final section


(Section


11)


will


consider


some


ways


in


which


further


linguistic


work


may


play


a


part


in


clarifying


some


of


these


problems.


II


Although this book makes no direct reference to experimental work, it can be understood only in terms of the general


framework that Skinner has developed for the description of behavior. Skinner divides the responses of the animal into


two


main


categories.


Respondents


are


purely


reflex


responses


elicited


by


particular


stimuli.


Operants


are


emitted


responses,


for


which


no


obvious


stimulus


can


be


discovered.


Skinner


has


been


concerned


primarily


with


operant


behavior. The experimental arrangement that he introduced consists basically of a box with a bar attached to one wall


in such a way that when the bar is pressed, a food pellet is dropped into a tray (and the bar press is recorded). A rat


placed in the box will soon press the bar, releasing a pellet into the tray. This state of affairs, resulting from the bar


press, increases the strength of the bar-pressing operant. The food pellet is called a reinforcer; the event, a reinforcing


event. The strength of an operant is defined by Skinner in terms of the rate of response during extinction (i.e, after the


last reinforcement and before return to the pre-conditioning rate).


Suppose that release of the pellet is conditional on the flashing of a light. Then the rat will come to press the bar only


when the light flashes. This is called stimulus discrimination. The response is called a discriminated operant and the


light is called the occasion for its emission: this is to be distinguished from elicitation of a response by a stimulus in the


case of the respondent.2 Suppose that the apparatus is so arranged that bar-pressing of only a certain character (e.g.,


duration) will release the pellet. The rat will then come to press the bar in the required way. This process is called


response differentiation. By successive slight changes in the conditions under which the response will be reinforced, it is


possible to shape the response of a rat or a pigeon in very surprising ways in a very short time, so that rather complex


behavior can be produced by a process of successive approximation.


A


stimulus can


become


reinforcing by


repeated


association


with


an


already


reinforcing stimulus.


Such


a stimulus


is


called a secondary reinforcer. Like many contemporary behaviorists, Skinner considers money, approval, and the like to


be


secondary


reinforcers


which


have


become


reinforcing


because


of


their


association


with


food,


etc.3


Secondary


reinforcers can be generalized by associating them with a variety of different primary reinforcers.


Another variable that can affect the rate of the bar- pressing operant is drive, which Skinner defines operationally in


terms


of


hours


of


deprivation.


His


major


scientific


book,


Behavior


of


Organisms,


is


a


study


of


the


effects


of


food- deprivation


and


conditioning


on


the


strength


of


the


bar- pressing


response


of


healthy


mature


rats.


Probably


Skinner's most original contribution to animal behavior studies has been his investigation of the effects of intermittent


reinforcement, arranged in various different ways, presented in Behavior of Organisms and extended (with pecking of


pigeons as the operant under investigation) in the recent Schedules of Reinforcement by Ferster and Skinner (1957). It is


apparently


these


studies


that


Skinner


has


in


mind


when


he


refers


to


the


recent


advances


in


the


study


of


animal


behavior.4


The notions stimulus, response, reinforcement are relatively well defined with respect to the bar-pressing experiments


and others similarly restricted. Before we can extend them to real-life behavior, however, certain difficulties must be


faced. We must decide, first of all, whether any physical event to which the organism is capable of reacting is to be


called a stimulus on a given occasion, or only one to which the organism in fact reacts; and correspondingly, we must


decide whether any part of behavior is to be called a response, or only one connected with stimuli in lawful ways.


Questions


of


this


sort


pose


something


of


a


dilemma


for


the


experimental


psychologist.


If


he


accepts


the


broad


definitions, characterizing any physical event impinging on the organism as a stimulus and any part of the organism's


behavior as a response, he must conclude that behavior has not been demonstrated to be lawful. In the present state of


our knowledge, we must attribute an overwhelming influence on actual behavior to ill- defined factors of attention, set,


volition,


and


caprice.


If


we


accept


the


narrower


definitions,


then


behavior


is


lawful


by


definition


(if


it


consists


of


responses); but this fact is of limited significance, since most of what the animal does will simply not be considered


behavior. Hence, the psychologist either must admit that behavior is not lawful (or that he cannot at present show that


it is -- not at all a damaging admission for a developing science), or must restrict his attention to those highly limited


areas


in


which


it


is


lawful


(e.g.,


with


adequate


controls,


bar-pressing


in


rats;


lawfulness


of


the


observed


behavior


provides, for Skinner, an implicit definition of a good experiment).


Skinner does not consistently adopt either course. He utilizes the experimental results as evidence for the scientific


character


of


his


system


of


behavior,


and


analogic


guesses


(formulated


in


terms


of


a


metaphoric


extension


of


the


technical vocabulary of the laboratory) as evidence for its scope. This creates the illusion of a rigorous scientific theory


with a very broad scope, although in fact the terms used in the description of real-life and of laboratory behavior may


be mere homonyms, with at most a vague similarity of meaning. To substantiate this evaluation, a critical account of his


book must show that with a literal reading (where the terms of the descriptive system have something like the technical


meanings


given


in


Skinner's


definitions)


the


book


covers


almost


no


aspect


of


linguistic


behavior,


and


that


with


a


metaphoric reading, it is no more scientific than the traditional approaches to this subject matter, and rarely as clear


and careful.5


III


Consider first Skinner's use of the notions stimulus and response. In Behavior of Organisms (9) he commits himself to the


narrow definitions for these terms. A part of the environment and a part of behavior are called stimulus (eliciting,


discriminated, or reinforcing) and response, respectively, only if they are lawfully related; that is, if the dynamic laws


relating them show smooth and reproducible curves. Evidently, stimuli and responses, so defined, have not been shown


to figure very widely in ordinary human behavior.6 We can, in the face of presently available evidence, continue to


maintain


the


lawfulness


of


the


relation


between


stimulus


and


response


only


by


depriving


them


of


their


objective


character.


A


typical


example


of


stimulus


control


for


Skinner


would


be


the


response


to


a


piece


of


music


with


the


utterance Mozart or to a painting with the response Dutch. These responses are asserted to be


extremely subtle properties


with the wallpaper, I thought you liked abstract work, Never saw it before, Tilted, Hanging too low, Beautiful, Hideous,


Remember our camping trip last summer?, or whatever else might come into our minds when looking at a picture (in


Skinnerian translation, whatever other responses exist in sufficient strength). Skinner could only say that each of these


responses is under the control of some other stimulus property of the physical object. If we look at a red chair and say


red, the response is under the control of the stimulus redness; if we say chair, it is under the control of the collection of


properties (for Skinner, the object) chairness (110), and similarly for any other response. This device is as simple as it is


empty.


Since


properties


are


free


for


the


asking


(we


have


as


many


of


them


as


we


have


nonsynonymous


descriptive


expressions in our language, whatever this means exactly), we can account for a wide class of responses in terms of


Skinnerian functional analysis by identifying the controlling stimuli. But the word stimulus has lost all objectivity in this


usage. Stimuli are no longer part of the outside physical world; they are driven back into the organism. We identify the


stimulus when we hear the response. It is clear from such examples, which abound, that the talk of stimulus control


simply disguises a complete retreat to mentalistic psychology. We cannot predict verbal behavior in terms of the stimuli


in the speaker's environment, since we do not know what the current stimuli are until he responds. Furthermore, since


we cannot control the property of a physical object to which an individual will respond, except in highly artificial cases,


Skinner's claim that his system, as opposed to the traditional one, permits the practical control of verbal behavior7 is


quite false.


Other examples of stimulus control merely add to the general mystification. Thus, a proper noun is held to be a response



and Moscow, which I presume are proper nouns if anything is, but have never been stimulated by the corresponding


objects. How can this fact be made compatible with this definition? Suppose that I use the name of a friend who is not


present. Is this an instance of a proper noun under the control of the friend as stimulus? Elsewhere it is asserted that a


stimulus controls a response in the sense that presence of the stimulus increases the probability of the response. But it


is obviously untrue that the probability that a speaker will produce a full name is increased when its bearer faces the


speaker. Furthermore, how can one's own name be a proper noun in this sense?


A


multitude


of


similar


questions


arise


immediately.


It


appears


that


the


word


control


here


is


merely


a


misleading


paraphrase for the traditional denote or refer. The assertion (115) that so far as the speaker is concerned, the relation


of reference is


having specified properties


sense. That they are not intended to be taken literally is indicated by many examples, as when a response is said to be



by


a


situation


or


state


of


affairs


as



Thus,


the


expression


a


needle


in


a


haystack



be


controlled as a unit by a particular type of situation


under the control of a single set of subtle properties of stimuli (121);


control of an extremely complex stimulus situation


under the control of a state of affairs which might also control He is ailing


foreign country and reports upon his return, his report is under


war may be a response to a


of stimuli which we speak of as action-in-the-past


specific


features


of


the


situation


as


its



(332).


No


characterization


of


the


notion


stimulus


control


that


is


remotely related to the bar-pressing experiment (or that preserves the faintest objectivity) can be made to cover a set


of


examples


like


these,


in


which,


for


example,


the


controlling


stimulus


need


not


even


impinge


on


the


responding


organism.


Consider now Skinner's use of the notion response. The problem of identifying units in verbal behavior has of course


been a primary concern of linguists, and it seems very likely that experimental psychologists should be able to provide


much-needed assistance in clearing up the many remaining difficulties in systematic identification. Skinner recognizes


(20) the fundamental character of the problem of identification of a unit of verbal behavior, but is satisfied with an


answer so vague and subjective that it does not really contribute to its solution. The unit of verbal behavior -- the verbal


operant


--


is


defined


as


a


class


of


responses


of


identifiable


form


functionally


related


to


one


or


more


controlling


variables. No method is suggested for determining in a particular instance what are the controlling variables, how many


such units have occurred, or where their boundaries are in the total response. Nor is any attempt made to specify how


much or what kind of similarity in form or control is required for two physical events to be considered instances of the


same operant. In short, no answers are suggested for the most elementary questions that must be asked of anyone


proposing a method for description of behavior. Skinner is content with what he calls an extrapolation of the concept of


operant developed in the laboratory to the verbal field. In the typical Skinnerian experiment, the problem of identifying


the unit of behavior is not too crucial. It is defined, by fiat, as a recorded peck or bar-press, and systematic variations in


the


rate


of


this


operant


and


its


resistance


to


extinction


are


studied


as


a


function


of


deprivation


and


scheduling


of


reinforcement


(pellets).


The


operant


is


thus


defined


with


respect


to


a


particular


experimental


procedure.


This


is


perfectly


reasonable


and


has


led


to


many


interesting


results.


It


is,


however,


completely


meaningless


to


speak


of


extrapolating


this


concept


of


operant


to


ordinary


verbal


behavior.


Such



leaves


us


with


no


way


of


justifying one or another decision about the units in the


Skinner specifies


bar-pressing


experiment,


response


strength


is


defined


in


terms


of


rate


of


emission


during


extinction.


Skinner


has


argued8 that this is


relevant to the 'learning process.'


(22). This definition provides a comforting impression of objectivity, which, however, is quickly dispelled when we look


into the matter more closely. The term probability has some rather obscure meaning for Skinner in this book.9 We are


told,


on


the


one


hand,


that



evidence


for


the


contribution


of


each


variable


[to


response


strength]


is


based


on


observation of frequencies alone


strength, since, for example, the frequency of a response may be


of controlling variables


frequency of occurrence of its controlling variables if we accept Skinner's view that the behavior occurring in a given


situation is


the contribution of each variable to response strength is based on observation of frequencies alone, it turns out that


base


the


notion


of


strength


upon


several


kinds


of


evidence


(22),


in


particular


(22-28):


emission


of


the


response


(particularly in unusual circumstances), energy level (stress), pitch level, speed and delay of emission, size of letters


etc. in writing, immediate repetition, and -- a final factor, relevant but misleading -- over-all frequency.


Of


course,


Skinner


recognizes


that


these


measures


do


not


co-vary,


because


(among


other


reasons)


pitch,


stress,


quantity, and reduplication may have internal linguistic functions.10 However, he does not hold these conflicts to be


very important, since the proposed factors indicative of strength are


For example,


be lost on the owner.


Beautiful


in


a


loud,


high- pitched


voice,


repeatedly,


and


with


no


delay


(high


response


strength).


It


may


be


equally


effective


to


look


at


the picture


silently


(long


delay)


and


then


to


murmur Beautiful


in


a soft,


low-pitched


voice


(by


definition, very low response strength).


It is not unfair, I believe, to conclude from Skinner's discussion of response strength, the basic datum in functional


analysis, that his extrapolation of the notion of probability can best be interpreted as, in effect, nothing more than a


decision to use the word probability, with its favorable connotations of objectivity, as a cover term to paraphrase such


low-status words as interest, intention, belief, and the like. This interpretation is fully justified by the way in which


Skinner uses the terms probability and strength. To cite just one example, Skinner defines the process of confirming an


assertion in science as one of


strength (425-29). If we take this suggestion quite literally, the degree of confirmation of a scientific assertion can be


measured


as


a


simple


function


of


the


loudness,


pitch,


and


frequency


with


which


it


is


proclaimed,


and


a


general


procedure for increasing its degree of confirmation would be, for instance, to train machine guns on large crowds of


people who have been instructed to shout it. A better indication of what Skinner probably has in mind here is given by


his description of how the theory of evolution, as an example, is confirmed. This


made more plausible -- is strengthened


-- by several types of construction based upon verbal responses in geology,


paleontology, genetics, and so on


as paraphrases of more familiar locutions such as


Similar latitude of interpretation is presumably expected when we read that


turn for what we may call the listener's 'belief'


or identical with, our tendency to act upon the verbal stimuli which he provides


I think it is evident, then, that Skinner's use of the terms stimulus, control, response, and strength justify the general


conclusion stated in the last paragraph of Section 2. The way in which these terms are brought to bear on the actual


data indicates that we must interpret them as mere paraphrases for the popular vocabulary commonly used to describe


behavior and as having no particular connection with the homonymous expressions used in the description of laboratory


experiments. Naturally, this terminological revision adds no objectivity to the familiar mentalistic mode of description.


IV


The other fundamental notion borrowed from the description of bar- pressing experiments is reinforcement. It raises


problems which are similar, and even more serious. In Behavior of Organisms,


as the presentation of a certain kind of stimulus in a temporal relation with either a stimulus or response. A reinforcing


stimulus is defined as such by its power to produce the resulting change [in strength]. There is no circularity about this:


some stimuli are found to produce the change, others not, and they are classified as reinforcing and nonreinforcing


accordingly


useless, however, in the discussion of real-life behavior, unless we can somehow characterize the stimuli which are


reinforcing (and the situations and conditions under which they are reinforcing). Consider first of all the status of the


basic principle that Skinner calls the


followed by presence of a reinforcing stimulus, the strength is increased


was defined, this law becomes a tautology.13 For Skinner, learning is just change in response strength.14 Although the


statement that presence of reinforcement is a sufficient condition for learning and maintenance of behavior is vacuous,


the


claim


that


it


is


a


necessary


condition


may


have


some


content,


depending


on


how


the


class


of


reinforcers


(and


appropriate situations) is characterized. Skinner does make it very clear that in his view reinforcement is a necessary


condition for language learning and for the continued availability of linguistic responses in the adult.15 However, the


looseness of the term reinforcement as Skinner uses it in the book under review makes it entirely pointless to inquire


into the truth or falsity of this claim. Examining the instances of what Skinner calls reinforcement, we find that not even


the requirement that a reinforcer be an identifiable stimulus is taken seriously. In fact, the term is used in such a way


that the assertion that reinforcement is necessary for learning and continued availability of behavior is likewise empty.


To


show


this,


we


consider


some


examples


of


reinforcement.


First


of


all,


we


find


a


heavy


appeal


to


automatic


self- reinforcement,


Thus,



man


talks


to


himself...


because


of


the


reinforcement


he


receives


(163);



child


is


reinforced automatically when he duplicates the sounds of airplanes, streetcars ...


nursery may automatically reinforce his own exploratory verbal behavior when he produces sounds which he has heard


in the speech of others


response'


and


is


reinforced


thereby


(68);


thinking


is



which


automatically


affects


the


behaver


and


is


reinforcing because it does so


verbal fantasy, whether overt or covert, is automatically reinforcing to the speaker as listener. Just as the musician


plays or composes what he is reinforced by hearing, or as the artist paints what reinforces him visually, so the speaker


engaged


in


verbal


fantasy


says


what


he


is


reinforced


by


hearing


or


writes


what


he


is


reinforced


by


reading


(439);


similarly, care in problem solving, and rationalization, are automatically self- reinforcing (442-43). We can also reinforce


someone by emitting verbal behavior as such (since this rules out a class of aversive stimulations, 167), by not emitting


verbal behavior (keeping silent and paying attention, 199), or by acting appropriately on some future occasion (152:


strength of [the speaker's] behavior is determined mainly by the behavior which the listener will exhibit with respect to


a given state of affairs


most such cases, of course, the speaker is not present at the time when the reinforcement takes place, as when


artist...is reinforced by the effects his works have upon... others


that his


may not be reinforced often or immediately, but his net reinforcement may be great



news, or to publish an experimental result which upsets the theory of a rival (154), to describe circumstances which


would be reinforcing if they were to occur (165), to avoid repetition (222), to


not mentioned or to hear nonexistent words in his child's babbling (259), to clarify or otherwise intensify the effect of a


stimulus which serves an important discriminative function (416), and so on.


From this sample, it can be seen that the notion of reinforcement has totally lost whatever objective meaning it may


ever have had. Running through these examples, we see that a person can be reinforced though he emits no response at


all, and that the reinforcing stimulus need not impinge on the reinforced person or need not even exist (it is sufficient


that it be imagined or hoped for). When we read that a person plays what music he likes (165), says what he likes (165),


thinks what he likes (438-39), reads what books he likes (163), etc., BECAUSE he finds it reinforcing to do so, or that we


write books or inform others of facts BECAUSE we are reinforced by what we hope will be the ultimate behavior of


reader or listener, we can only conclude that the term reinforcement has a purely ritual function. The phrase


reinforced by Y (stimulus, state of affairs, event, etc.)


wishes that Y were the case,


paraphrase introduces any new clarity or objectivity into the description of wishing, liking, etc., is a serious delusion.


The only effect is to obscure the important differences among the notions being paraphrased. Once we recognize the


latitude with which the term reinforcement is being used, many rather startling comments lose their initial effect -- for


instance, that the behavior of the creative artist is


What has been hoped for from the psychologist is some indication how the casual and informal description of everyday


behavior in the popular vocabulary can be explained or clarified in terms of the notions developed in careful experiment


and observation, or perhaps replaced in terms of a better scheme. A mere terminological revision, in which a term


borrowed from the laboratory is used with the full vagueness of the ordinary vocabulary, is of no conceivable interest.


It seems that Skinner's claim that all verbal behavior is acquired and maintained in


quite empty, because his notion of reinforcement has no clear content, functioning only as a cover term for any factor,


detectable or not, related to acquisition or maintenance of verbal behavior.16 Skinner's use of the term conditioning


suffers


from


a


similar


difficulty.


Pavlovian


and


operant


conditioning


are


processes


about


which


psychologists


have


developed


real


understanding.


Instruction


of


human


beings


is


not.


The


claim


that


instruction


and


imparting


of


information


are


simply


matters


of


conditioning


(357-66)


is


pointless.


The


claim


is


true,


if


we


extend


the


term


conditioning to cover these processes, but we know no more about them after having revised this term in such a way as


to deprive it of its relatively clear and objective character. It is, as far as we know, quite false, if we use conditioning in


its literal sense. Similarly, when we say that


one term to another or from one object to another


true of the predication Whales are mammals? Or, to take Skinner's example, what point is there in saying that the effect


of The telephone is out of order on the listener is to bring behavior formerly controlled by the stimulus out of order


under control of the stimulus telephone (or the telephone itself) by a process of simple conditioning (362)? What laws of


conditioning hold in this case? Furthermore, what behavior is controlled by the stimulus out of order, in the abstract?


Depending on the object of which this is predicated, the present state of motivation of the listener, etc., the behavior


may vary from rage to pleasure, from fixing the object to throwing it out, from simply not using it to trying to use it in


the normal way (e.g., to see if it is really out of order), and so on. To speak of


available behavior under control of a new stimulus


V


The claim that careful arrangement of contingencies of reinforcement by the verbal community is a necessary condition


for


language-learning


has


appeared,


in


one


form


or


another,


in


many


places.17


Since


it


is


based


not


on


actual


observation, but on analogies to laboratory study of lower organisms, it is important to determine the status of the


underlying assertion within experimental psychology proper. The most common characterization of reinforcement (one


which


Skinner


explicitly


rejects,


incidentally)


is


in


terms


of


drive


reduction.


This


characterization


can


be


given


substance by defining drives in some way independently of what in fact is learned. If a drive is postulated on the basis of


the fact that learning takes place, the claim that reinforcement is necessary for learning will again become as empty as


it is in the Skinnerian framework. There is an extensive literature on the question of whether there can be learning


without drive reduction (latent learning). The


maze


without


reward


showed


a


marked


drop


in


number


of


errors


(as


compared


to


a


control


group


which


had


not


explored the maze) upon introduction of a food reward, indicating that the rat had learned the structure of the maze


without reduction of the hunger drive. Drive-reduction theorists countered with an exploratory drive which was reduced


during the pre-reward learning, and claimed that a slight decrement in errors could be noted before food reward. A


wide variety of experiments, with somewhat conflicting results, have been carried out with a similar design.18 Few


investigators still doubt the existence of the phenomenon, E. R. Hilgard, in his general


review of learning theory,19


concludes


that



is


no


longer


any


doubt


but


that,


under


appropriate


circumstances,


latent


learning


is


demonstrable.


More recent work has shown that novelty and variety of stimulus are sufficient to arouse curiosity in the rat and to


motivate it to explore (visually), and in fact, to learn (since on a presentation of two stimuli, one novel, one repeated,


the rat will attend to the novel one),20 that rats will learn to choose the arm of a single-choice maze that leads to a


complex maze, running through this being their only


maintain their performance at a high level of efficiency with visual exploration (looking out of a window for 30 seconds)


as the only reward22 and, perhaps most strikingly of all, that monkeys and apes will solve rather complex manipulation


problems


that


are


simply


placed


in


their


cages,


and


will


solve


discrimination


problems


with


only


exploration


and


manipulation as incentives.23 In these cases, solving the problem is apparently its own


be handled by reinforcement theorists only if they are willing to set up curiosity, exploration, and manipulation drives,


or to speculate somehow about acquired drives24 for which there is no evidence outside of the fact that learning takes


place in these cases.


There


is


a


variety


of


other


kinds


of


evidence


that


has


been


offered


to


challenge


the


view


that


drive


reduction


is


necessary


for


learning.


Results


on


sensory-sensory


conditioning


have


been


interpreted


as


demonstrating


learning


without drive reduction.25 Olds has reported reinforcement by direct stimulation of the brain, from which he concludes


that reward need not satisfy a physiological need or withdraw a drive stimulus.26 The phenomenon of imprinting, long


observed by zoologists, is of particular interest in this connection. Some of the most complex patterns of behavior of


birds, in particular, are directed towards objects and animals of the type to which they have been exposed at certain


critical early periods of life.27 Imprinting is the most striking evidence for the innate disposition of the animal to learn


in a certain direction and to react appropriately to patterns and objects of certain restricted types, often only long after


the


original


learning


has


taken


place.


It


is,


consequently,


unrewarded


learning,


though


the


resulting


patterns


of


behavior may be refined through reinforcement. Acquisition of the typical songs of song birds is, in some cases, a type of


imprinting. Thorpe reports studies that show


earliest youth, before the bird itself is able to produce any kind of full song.


recently been investigated under laboratory conditions and controls with positive results.29


Phenomena of this general type are certainly familiar from everyday experience. We recognize people and places to


which we have given no particular attention. We can look up something in a book and learn it perfectly well with no


other motive than to confute reinforcement theory, or out of boredom, or idle curiosity. Everyone engaged in research


must have had the experience of working with feverish and prolonged intensity to write a paper which no one else will


read or to solve a problem which no one else thinks important and which will bring no conceivable reward -- which may


only confirm a general opinion that the researcher is wasting his time on irrelevancies. The fact that rats and monkeys


do


likewise


is


interesting


and


important


to


show


in


careful


experiment.


In


fact,


studies


of


behavior


of


the


type


mentioned


above


have


an


independent


and


positive


significance


that


far


outweighs


their


incidental


importance


in


bringing into question the claim that learning is impossible without drive reduction. It is not at all unlikely that insights


arising


from


animal


behavior


studies


with


this


broadened


scope


may


have


the


kind


of


relevance


to


such


complex


activities


as


verbal


behavior


that


reinforcement


theory


has,


so


far,


failed


to


exhibit.


In


any


event,


in


the


light


of


presently available evidence, it is difficult to see how anyone can be willing to claim that reinforcement is necessary for


learning,


if


reinforcement


is


taken


seriously


as


something


identifiable


independently


of


the


resulting


change


in


behavior.


Similarly, it seems quite beyond question that children acquire a good deal of their verbal and nonverbal behavior by


casual observation and imitation of adults and other children.30 It is simply not true that children can learn language


only


through



care


on


the


part


of


adults


who


shape


their


verbal


repertoire


through


careful


differential


reinforcement, though it may be that such care is often the custom in academic families. It is a common observation


that a young child of immigrant parents may learn a second language in the streets, from other children, with amazing


rapidity, and that his speech may be completely fluent and correct to the last allophone, while the subtleties that


become second nature to the child may elude his parents despite high motivation and continued practice. A child may


pick up a large part of his vocabulary and


adults, etc. Even a very young child who has not yet acquired a minimal repertoire from which to form new utterances


may imitate a word quite well on an early try, with no attempt on the part of his parents to teach it to him. It is also


perfectly obvious that, at a later stage, a child will be able to construct and understand utterances which are quite new,


and


are,


at


the


same


time,


acceptable


sentences


in


his


language.


Every


time


an


adult


reads


a


newspaper,


he


undoubtedly comes upon countless new sentences which are not at all similar, in a simple, physical sense, to any that he


has


heard


before,


and


which


he


will


recognize


as


sentences


and


understand;


he


will


also


be


able


to


detect


slight


distortions or misprints. Talk of


title. These abilities indicate that there must be fundamental processes at work quite independently of


the environment. I have been able to find no support whatsoever for the doctrine of Skinner and others that slow and


careful shaping of verbal behavior through differential reinforcement is an absolute necessity. If reinforcement theory


really requires the assumption that there be such meticulous care, it seems best to regard this simply as a reductio ad


absurdum argument against this approach. It is also not easy to find any basis (or, for that matter, to attach very much


content) to the claim that reinforcing contingencies set up by the verbal community are the single factor responsible for


maintaining the strength of verbal behavior. The sources of the


present. Reinforcement undoubtedly plays a significant role, but so do a variety of motivational factors about which


nothing serious is known in the case of human beings.


As


far


as


acquisition


of


language


is


concerned,


it


seems


clear


that


reinforcement,


casual


observation,


and


natural


inquisitiveness (coupled with a strong tendency to imitate) are important factors, as is the remarkable capacity of the


child to generalize, hypothesize, and


ways which we cannot yet describe or begin to understand, and which may be largely innate, or may develop through


some sort


of


learning


or through


maturation


of the nervous


system.


The manner


in


which such factors


operate


and


interact in language acquisition is completely unknown. It is clear that what is necessary in such a case is research, not


dogmatic and perfectly arbitrary claims, based on analogies to that small part of the experimental literature in which


one happens to be interested.


The pointlessness of these claims becomes clear when we consider the well-known difficulties in determining to what


extent


inborn


structure,


maturation,


and


learning


are


responsible


for


the


particular


form


of


a


skilled


or


complex


performance.31 To take just one example,32 the gaping response of a nestling thrush is at first released by jarring of


the nest, and, at a later stage, by a moving object of specific size, shape, and position relative to the nestling. At this


later stage the response is directed toward the part of the stimulus object corresponding to the parent's head, and


characterized by a complex configuration of stimuli that can be precisely described. Knowing just this, it would be


possible to construct a speculative, learning-theoretic account of how this sequence of behavior patterns might have


developed


through


a


process


of


differential


reinforcement,


and


it


would


no


doubt


be


possible


to


train


rats


to


do


something similar. However, there appears to be good evidence that these responses to fairly complex


genetically determined and mature without learning. Clearly, the possibility cannot be discounted. Consider now the


comparable case of a child imitating new words. At an early stage we may find rather gross correspondences. At a later


stage, we find that repetition is of course far from exact (i.e., it is not mimicry, a fact which itself is interesting), but


that it reproduces the highly complex configuration of sound features that constitute the phonological structure of the


language in question. Again, we can propose a speculative account of how this result might have been obtained through


elaborate arrangement of reinforcing contingencies. Here too, however, it is possible that ability to select out of the


complex


auditory


input


those


features


that


are


phonologically


relevant


may


develop


largely


independently


of


reinforcement,


through


genetically


determined


maturation.


To


the


extent


that


this


is


true,


an


account


of


the


development


and


causation


of


behavior


that


fails


to


consider


the


structure


of


the


organism


will


provide


no


understanding of the real processes involved.


It is often argued that experience, rather than innate capacity to handle information in certain specific ways, must be


the


factor


of


overwhelming


dominance


in


determining


the


specific


character


of


language


acquisition,


since


a


child


speaks the language of the group in which he lives. But this is a superficial argument. As long as we are speculating, we


may


consider


the


possibility


that


the


brain


has


evolved


to


the


point


where,


given


an


input


of


observed


Chinese


sentences,


it


produces


(by


an


induction


of


apparently


fantastic


complexity


and


suddenness)


the


rules


of


Chinese


grammar,


and


given


an


input


of


observed


English


sentences,


it


produces


(by,


perhaps, exactly


the


same


process


of


induction)


the


rules


of


English


grammar;


or


that


given


an


observed


application


of


a


term


to


certain


instances,


it


automatically


predicts


the


extension


to


a


class


of


complexly


related


instances.


If


clearly


recognized


as


such,


this


speculation is neither unreasonable nor fantastic; nor, for that matter, is it beyond the bounds of possible study. There


is of course no known neural structure capable of performing this task in the specific ways that


observation of the


resulting behavior might lead us to postulate; but for that matter, the structures capable of accounting for even the


simplest kinds of learning have similarly defied detection.33 Summarizing this brief discussion, it seems that there is


neither empirical evidence nor any known argument to support any specific claim about the relative importance of



from


the


environment


and


the



contribution


of


the


organism


in


the


process


of


language


acquisition.


VI


We now turn to the system that Skinner develops specifically for the description of verbal behavior. Since this system is


based on the notions stimulus, response, and reinforcement, we can conclude from the preceding sections that it will be


vague and arbitrary. For reasons noted in Section 1, however, I think it is important to see in detail how far from the


mark any analysis phrased solely in these terms must be and how completely this system fails to account for the facts of


verbal


behavior.


Consider


first


the


term


verbal


behavior


itself.


This


is


defined


as



reinforced


through


the


mediation


of


other


persons


(2).


The


definition


is


clearly


much


too


broad.


It


would


include


as


verbal


behavior,


for


example, a rat pressing the bar in a Skinner-box, a child brushing his teeth, a boxer retreating before an opponent, and


a mechanic repairing an automobile. Exactly how much of ordinary linguistic behavior is verbal in this sense, however, is


something of a question: perhaps, as I have pointed out above, a fairly small fraction of it, if any substantive meaning is


assigned to the term reinforced. This definition is subsequently refined by the additional provision that the mediating


response of the reinforcing person (the listener) must itself


behavior


of


the


speaker


(225,


italics


his).


This


still


covers


the


examples


given


above,


if


we


can


assume


that


the


reinforcing behavior of the psychologist, the parent, the


opposing boxer, and the paying customer are the result of


appropriate


training,


which


is


perhaps


not


unreasonable.


A


significant


part


of


the


fragment


of


linguistic


behavior


covered by the earlier definition will no doubt be excluded by the refinement, however. Suppose, for example, that


while crossing the street I hear someone shout Watch out for the car and jump out of the way. It can hardly be proposed


that my jumping (the mediating, reinforcing response in Skinner's usage) was conditioned (that is, I was trained to jump)


precisely in order to reinforce the behavior of the speaker; and similarly, for a wide class of cases. Skinner's assertion


that with this refined definition


appears to be grossly in error.


VII


Verbal


operants


are


classified


by


Skinner


in


terms


of


their



relation


to


discriminated


stimulus,


reinforcement, and other verbal responses. A mand is defined as


a


characteristic


consequence


and


is


therefore


under


the


functional


control


of


relevant


conditions


of


deprivation


or


aversive stimulation


a host of problems. A mand such as Pass the salt is a class of responses. We cannot tell by observing the form of a


response


whether


it


belongs


to


this


class


(Skinner


is


very


clear


about


this),


but


only


by


identifying


the


controlling


variables. This is generally impossible. Deprivation is defined in the bar- pressing experiment in terms of length of time


that the animal has not been fed or permitted to drink. In the present context, however, it is quite a mysterious notion.


No attempt is made here to describe a method for determining



experimenter. If we define deprivation in terms of elapsed time, then at any moment a person is in countless states of


deprivation.34 It appears that we must decide that the relevant condition of deprivation was (say) salt-deprivation, on


the basis of the fact that the speaker asked for salt (the reinforcing community which


predicament). In this case, the assertion that a mand is under the control of relevant deprivation is empty, and we are


(contrary to Skinner's intention) identifying the response as a mand completely in terms of form. The word relevant in


the definition above conceals some rather serious complications.


In the case of the mand Pass the salt, the word deprivation is not out of place, though it appears to be of little use for


functional analysis. Suppose however that the speaker says Give me the book, Take me for a ride, or Let me fix it. What


kinds of deprivation can be associated with these mands? How do we determine or measure the relevant deprivation? I


think


we must conclude in


this case,


as


before, either that the


notion


deprivation


is


relevant


at most


to


a minute


fragment of verbal behavior, or else that the statement


Y,


The notion aversive control is just as confused. This is intended to cover threats, beating, and the like (33). The manner


in which aversive stimulation functions is simply described. If a speaker has had a history of appropriate reinforcement


(e.g., if a certain response was followed by


been followed by such injury and which are therefore conditioned aversive stimuli


response when the threat which had previously been followed by the injury is presented. It would appear to follow from


this description that a speaker will not respond properly to the mand Your money or your life (38) unless he has a past


history of being killed. But even if the difficulties in describing the mechanism of aversive control are somehow removed


by a more careful analysis, it will be of little use for identifying operants for reasons similar to those mentioned in the


case of deprivation.


It seems, then, that in Skinner's terms there is in most cases no way to decide whether a given response is an instance of


a particular mand. Hence it is meaningless, within the terms of his system, to speak of the characteristic consequences


of


a


mand,


as


in


the


definition


above.


Furthermore,


even


if


we


extend


the system so


that mands can


somehow


be


identified,


we


will


have


to


face


the


obvious


fact


that


most


of


us


are


not


fortunate


enough


to


have


our


requests,


commands, advice, and so on characteristically reinforced (they may nevertheless exist in considerable strength). These


responses could therefore not be considered mands by Skinner. In fact, Skinner sets up a category of


(48-49) to cover the case of


be accounted for by showing that


they have


ever had the effect


specified


or


any


similar


effect


upon


similar


occasions


(the


word


ever


in


this


statement


should


be


replaced


by


characteristically).


In


these


pseudo-mands,



speaker


simply


describes


the


reinforcement


appropriate


to


a


given


state of deprivation or aversive stimulation.


reinforcement and deprivation, the speaker asks for what he wants. The remark that


mands on the analogy of old ones


Skinner's claim that his new descriptive system is superior to the traditional one


respect to experimental operations


pointing


out


a


relation


between


rate


of


bar-pressing


and


hours


of


food- deprivation;


replacing



wants


Y


by



is


deprived of Y


analysis of mands is that it provides an objective basis for the traditional classification into requests, commands, etc.


(38-41). The traditional classification is in terms of the intention of the speaker. But intention, Skinner holds, can be


reduced to contingencies of reinforcement, and, correspondingly, we can explain the traditional classification in terms

-


-


-


-


-


-


-


-



本文更新与2021-02-01 13:12,由作者提供,不代表本网站立场,转载请注明出处:https://www.bjmy2z.cn/gaokao/592625.html

A Review of B. F. Skinner's Verbal Behavior的相关文章

  • 爱心与尊严的高中作文题库

    1.关于爱心和尊严的作文八百字 我们不必怀疑富翁的捐助,毕竟普施爱心,善莫大焉,它是一 种美;我们也不必指责苛求受捐者的冷漠的拒绝,因为人总是有尊 严的,这也是一种美。

    小学作文
  • 爱心与尊严高中作文题库

    1.关于爱心和尊严的作文八百字 我们不必怀疑富翁的捐助,毕竟普施爱心,善莫大焉,它是一 种美;我们也不必指责苛求受捐者的冷漠的拒绝,因为人总是有尊 严的,这也是一种美。

    小学作文
  • 爱心与尊重的作文题库

    1.作文关爱与尊重议论文 如果说没有爱就没有教育的话,那么离开了尊重同样也谈不上教育。 因为每一位孩子都渴望得到他人的尊重,尤其是教师的尊重。可是在现实生活中,不时会有

    小学作文
  • 爱心责任100字作文题库

    1.有关爱心,坚持,责任的作文题库各三个 一则150字左右 (要事例) “胜不骄,败不馁”这句话我常听外婆说起。 这句名言的意思是说胜利了抄不骄傲,失败了不气馁。我真正体会到它

    小学作文
  • 爱心责任心的作文题库

    1.有关爱心,坚持,责任的作文题库各三个 一则150字左右 (要事例) “胜不骄,败不馁”这句话我常听外婆说起。 这句名言的意思是说胜利了抄不骄傲,失败了不气馁。我真正体会到它

    小学作文
  • 爱心责任作文题库

    1.有关爱心,坚持,责任的作文题库各三个 一则150字左右 (要事例) “胜不骄,败不馁”这句话我常听外婆说起。 这句名言的意思是说胜利了抄不骄傲,失败了不气馁。我真正体会到它

    小学作文